For whom was the earth created? Are some of us more entitled
than others to its riches? Is it those who work who are entitled, or those
who claim ownership of land and other natural resources? Should some of us
be able to charge others rent for the use of land and other natural resources,
and keep that rent as if it was something we had created, or should the annual
value of the land itself be passed along to the commons, as the foundation
for our common spending? Should ownership of land and other resources be
a source of wealth for a lucky few, or should land and natural resources
be fundamentally the common property of all the world's people, or of the
residents of each country?
Henry George: Ode to
Liberty (1877 speech)
In the very centers of our
civilization today are want and
suffering enough to make sick at heart whoever does not close his
eyes and steel his nerves. Dare we turn to the Creator and ask Him to
relieve it? Supposing the prayer were heard, and at the behest with
which the universe sprang into being there should glow in the sun a
greater power; new virtue fill the air; fresh vigor the soil; that
for every blade of grass that now grows two should spring up, and the
seed that now increases fifty-fold should increase a hundredfold!
Would poverty be abated or want relieved? Manifestly no! Whatever
benefit would accrue would be but temporary. The new powers streaming
through the material universe could be utilized only through land.
And land, being private property, the classes that now monopolize the
bounty of the Creator would monopolize all the new bounty. Land
owners would alone be benefited. Rents would increase, but wages
would still tend to the starvation point! ... read the whole speech
Henry George: The Condition of
Labor — An Open Letter to Pope Leo XIII in response to Rerum Novarum (1891)
Your use, in so many passages of your Encyclical, of the inclusive term “property” or “private” property,
of which in morals nothing can be either affirmed or denied, makes your meaning,
if we take isolated sentences, in many places ambiguous. But reading it as
a whole, there can be no doubt of your intention that private property in
land shall be understood when you speak merely of private property. With
this interpretation, I find that the reasons you urge for private property
in land are eight. Let us consider them in order of presentation. You urge:
1. That what is bought with rightful property is rightful property. (RN,
paragraph 5) ...
2. That private property in land proceeds from man’s gift of reason.
(RN, paragraphs 6-7.) ...
3. That private property in land deprives no one of the use of land. (RN,
paragraph 8.) ...
4. That Industry expended on land gives ownership in the land itself. (RN,
paragraphs 9-10.) ...
5. That private property in land has the support of the common opinion of
mankind, and has conduced to peace and tranquillity, and that it is sanctioned
by Divine Law. (RN, paragraph 11.) ...
6. That fathers should provide for their children and that private property
in land is necessary to enable them to do so. (RN, paragraphs 14-17.) ...
7. That the private ownership of land stimulates industry, increases wealth,
and attaches men to the soil and to their country. (RN, paragraph 51.) ...
8. That the right to possess private property in land is from nature, not
from man; that the state has no right to abolish it, and that to take the
value of landownership in taxation would be unjust and cruel to the private
owner. (RN, paragraph 51.) ...
2. That private property in land proceeds from man’s gift of reason. (6-7.)
In the second place your Holiness argues that man possessing reason and
forethought may not only acquire ownership of the fruits of the earth, but
also of the earth itself, so that out of its products he may make provision
for the future.
Reason, with its attendant forethought, is indeed the distinguishing attribute
of man; that which raises him above the brute, and shows, as the Scriptures
declare, that he is created in the likeness of God. And this gift of reason
does, as your Holiness points out, involve the need and right of private
property in whatever is produced by the exertion of reason and its attendant
forethought, as well as in what is produced by physical labor. In truth,
these elements of man’s production are inseparable, and labor involves
the use of reason. It is by his reason that man differs from the animals
in being a producer, and in this sense a maker. Of themselves his physical
powers are slight, forming as it were but the connection by which the mind
takes hold of material things, so as to utilize to its will the matter and
forces of nature. It is mind, the intelligent reason, that is the prime mover
in labor, the essential agent in production.
The right of private ownership does therefore indisputably attach to things
provided by man’s reason and forethought. But it cannot attach to things
provided by the reason and forethought of God!
To illustrate: Let us suppose a company traveling through the desert as
the Israelites traveled from Egypt. Such of them as had the forethought to
provide themselves with vessels of water would acquire a just right of property
in the water so carried, and in the thirst of the waterless desert those
who had neglected to provide themselves, though they might ask water from
the provident in charity, could not demand it in right. For while water itself
is of the providence of God, the presence of this water in such vessels,
at such place, results from the providence of the men who carried it. Thus
they have to it an exclusive right.
But suppose others use their forethought in pushing ahead and appropriating
the springs, refusing when their fellows come up to let them drink of the
water save as they buy it of them. Would such forethought give any right?
Your Holiness, it is not the forethought of carrying water where it is needed,
but the forethought of seizing springs, that you seek to defend in defending
the private ownership of land!
Let me show this more fully, since it may be worth while to meet those who
say that if private property in land be not just, then private property in
the products of labor is not just, as the material of these products is taken
from land. It will be seen on consideration that all of man’s production
is analogous to such transportation of water as we have supposed. In growing
grain, or smelting metals, or building houses, or weaving cloth, or doing
any of the things that constitute producing, all that man does is to change
in place or form preexisting matter. As a producer man is merely a changer,
not a creator; God alone creates. And since the changes in which man’s
production consists inhere in matter so long as they persist, the right of
private ownership attaches the accident to the essence, and gives the right
of ownership in that natural material in which the labor of production is
embodied. Thus water, which in its original form and place is the common
gift of God to all men, when drawn from its natural reservoir and brought
into the desert, passes rightfully into the ownership of the individual who
by changing its place has produced it there.
But such right of ownership is in reality a mere right of temporary
possession. For though man may take material from the storehouse of nature
and change
it in place or form to suit his desires, yet from the moment he takes it,
it tends back to that storehouse again. Wood decays, iron rusts, stone disintegrates
and is displaced, while of more perishable products, some will last for only
a few months, others for only a few days, and some disappear immediately
on use. Though, so far as we can see, matter is eternal and force forever
persists; though we can neither annihilate nor create the tiniest mote that
floats in a sunbeam or the faintest impulse that stirs a leaf, yet in the
ceaseless flux of nature, man’s work of moving and combining constantly
passes away. Thus the recognition of the ownership of what natural material
is embodied in the products of man never constitutes more than temporary
possession — never interferes with the reservoir provided for all.
As taking water from one place and carrying it to another place by no means
lessens the store of water, since whether it is drunk or spilled or left
to evaporate, it must return again to the natural reservoirs — so is
it with all things on which man in production can lay the impress of his
labor.
Hence, when you say that man’s reason puts it within his right to
have in stable and permanent possession not only things that perish in the
using, but also those that remain for use in the future, you are right in
so far as you may include such things as buildings, which with repair will
last for generations, with such things as food or fire-wood, which are destroyed
in the use. But when you infer that man can have private ownership in those
permanent things of nature that are the reservoirs from which all must draw,
you are clearly wrong. Man may indeed hold in private ownership the fruits
of the earth produced by his labor, since they lose in time the impress of
that labor, and pass again into the natural reservoirs from which they were
taken, and thus the ownership of them by one works no injury to others. But
he cannot so own the earth itself, for that is the reservoir from which must
constantly be drawn not only the material with which alone men can produce,
but even their very bodies.
The conclusive reason why man cannot claim ownership in the earth itself
as he can in the fruits that he by labor brings forth from it, is in the
facts stated by you in the very next paragraph (7), when you truly say:
Man’s needs do not die out, but recur; satisfied today, they
demand new supplies tomorrow. Nature, therefore, owes to man a storehouse
that shall
never fail, the daily supply of his daily wants. And this he finds only in
the inexhaustible fertility of the earth.
By man you mean all men. Can what nature owes to all men be made the private
property of some men, from which they may debar all other men?
Let me dwell on the words of your Holiness, “Nature, therefore, owes
to man a storehouse that shall never fail.” By Nature you mean God.
Thus your thought, that in creating us, God himself has incurred an obligation
to provide us with a storehouse that shall never fail, is the same as is
thus expressed and carried to its irresistible conclusion by the Bishop of
Meath:
God was perfectly free in the act by which He created us; but having created
us he bound himself by that act to provide us with the means necessary
for our subsistence. The land is the only source of this kind now known
to us.
The land, therefore, of every country is the common property of the people
of that country, because its real owner, the Creator who made it, has
transferred it as a voluntary gift to them. “Terram autem dedit
filiis hominum.” Now,
as every individual in that country is a creature and child of God, and
as all his creatures are equal in his sight, any settlement of the land
of a
country that would exclude the humblest man in that country from his
share of the common inheritance would be not only an injustice and a wrong
to that
man, but, moreover, be AN IMPIOUS RESISTANCE TO THE BENEVOLENT INTENTIONS
OF HIS CREATOR. ...
6. That fathers should provide for their children and that private
property in land is necessary to enable them to do so. (14-17.)
With all that your Holiness has to say of the sacredness of the family relation
we are in full accord. But how the obligation of the father to the child
can justify private property in land we cannot see. You reason that private
property in land is necessary to the discharge of the duty of the father,
and is therefore requisite and just, because —
It is a most sacred law of nature that a father must provide food and all
necessaries for those whom he has begotten; and, similarly, nature dictates
that a man’s children, who carry on, as it were, and continue his own
personality, should be provided by him with all that is needful to enable
them honorably to keep themselves from want and misery in the uncertainties
of this mortal life. Now, in no other way can a father effect this except
by the ownership of profitable property, which he can transmit to his children
by inheritance. (14.)
Thanks to Him who has bound the generations of men together by a provision
that brings the tenderest love to greet our entrance into the world and soothes
our exit with filial piety, it is both the duty and the joy of the father
to care for the child till its powers mature, and afterwards in the natural
order it becomes the duty and privilege of the child to be the stay of the
parent. This is the natural reason for that relation of marriage, the groundwork
of the sweetest, tenderest and purest of human joys, which the Catholic Church
has guarded with such unremitting vigilance.
We do, for a few years, need the providence of our fathers after the flesh.
But how small, how transient, how narrow is this need, as compared with our
constant need for the providence of Him in whom we live, move and have our
being — Our Father who art in Heaven! It is to him, “the giver
of every good and perfect gift,” and not to our fathers after the flesh,
that Christ taught us to pray, “Give us this day our daily bread.” And
how true it is that it is through him that the generations of men exist!
Let the mean temperature of the earth rise or fall a few degrees, an amount
as nothing compared with differences produced in our laboratories, and mankind
would disappear as ice disappears under a tropical sun, would fall as the
leaves fall at the touch of frost. Or, let for two or three seasons the earth
refuse her increase, and how many of our millions would remain alive?
The duty of fathers to transmit to their children profitable property that
will enable them to keep themselves from want and misery in the uncertainties
of this mortal life! What is not possible cannot be a duty. And how is it
possible for fathers to do that? Your Holiness has not considered how mankind
really lives from hand to mouth, getting each day its daily bread; how little
one generation does or can leave another. It is doubtful if the wealth of
the civilized world all told amounts to anything like as much as one year’s
labor, while it is certain that if labor were to stop and men had to rely
on existing accumulation, it would be only a few days ere in the richest
countries pestilence and famine would stalk.
The profitable property your Holiness refers to, is private property in
land. Now profitable land, as all economists will agree, is land superior
to the
land that the ordinary man can get. It is land that will yield an income
to the owner as owner, and therefore that will permit the owner to appropriate
the products of labor without doing labor, its profitableness to the individual
involving the robbery of other individuals. It is therefore possible only
for some fathers to leave their children profitable land. What therefore
your Holiness practically declares is, that it is the duty of all fathers
to struggle to leave their children what only the few peculiarly strong,
lucky or unscrupulous can leave; and that, a something that involves the
robbery of others — their deprivation of the material gifts of God.
This anti-Christian doctrine has been long in practice throughout the Christian
world. What are its results?
Are they not the very evils set forth in your Encyclical? Are they not,
so far from enabling men to keep themselves from want and misery in the uncertainties
of this mortal life, to condemn the great masses of men to want and misery
that the natural conditions of our mortal life do not entail; to want and
misery deeper and more wide-spread than exist among heathen savages? Under
the régime of private property in land and in the richest countries
not five per cent of fathers are able at their death to leave anything substantial
to their children, and probably a large majority do not leave enough to bury
them! Some few children are left by their fathers richer than it is good
for them to be, but the vast majority not only are left nothing by their
fathers, but by the system that makes land private property are deprived
of the bounty of their Heavenly Father; are compelled to sue others for permission
to live and to work, and to toil all their lives for a pittance that often
does not enable them to escape starvation and pauperism.
What your Holiness is actually, though of course inadvertently, urging,
is that earthly fathers should assume the functions of the Heavenly Father.
It is not the business of one generation to provide the succeeding generation “with
all that is needful to enable them honorably to keep themselves from want
and misery.” That is God’s business. We no more create our children
than we create our fathers. It is God who is the Creator of each succeeding
generation as fully as of the one that preceded it. And, to recall
your own words (7), “Nature [God], therefore, owes to man a storehouse that
shall never fail, the daily supply of his daily wants. And this he finds
only in the inexhaustible fertility of the earth.” What you are now
assuming is, that it is the duty of men to provide for the wants of their
children by appropriating this storehouse and depriving other men’s
children of the unfailing supply that God has provided for all.
The duty of the father to the child — the duty possible to all fathers!
Is it not so to conduct himself, so to nurture and teach it, that it shall
come to manhood with a sound body, well-developed mind, habits of virtue,
piety and industry, and in a state of society that shall give it and all
others free access to the bounty of God, the providence of the All-Father?
In doing this the father would be doing more to secure his children from
want and misery than is possible now to the richest of fathers — as
much more as the providence of God surpasses that of man. For the justice
of God laughs at the efforts of men to circumvent it, and the subtle law
that binds humanity together poisons the rich in the sufferings of the poor.
Even the few who are able in the general struggle to leave their children
wealth that they fondly think will keep them from want and misery in the
uncertainties of this mortal life — do they succeed? Does experience
show that it is a benefit to a child to place him above his fellows and enable
him to think God’s law of labor is not for him? Is not such wealth
oftener a curse than a blessing, and does not its expectation often destroy
filial love and bring dissensions and heartburnings into families? And how
far and how long are even the richest and strongest able to exempt their
children from the common lot? Nothing is more certain than that the blood
of the masters of the world flows today in lazzaroni and that the descendants
of kings and princes tenant slums and workhouses.
But in the state of society we strive for, where the monopoly and waste
of God’s bounty would be done away with and the fruits of labor would
go to the laborer, it would be within the ability of all to make more than
a comfortable living with reasonable labor. And for those who might be crippled
or incapacitated, or deprived of their natural protectors and breadwinners,
the most ample provision could be made out of that great and increasing fund
with which God in his law of rent has provided society — not as a matter
of niggardly and degrading alms, but as a matter of right, as the assurance
which in a Christian state society owes to all its members.
Thus it is that the duty of the father, the obligation to the child, instead
of giving any support to private property in land, utterly condemns it, urging
us by the most powerful considerations to abolish it in the simple and efficacious
way of the single tax.
This duty of the father, this obligation to children, is not confined to
those who have actually children of their own, but rests on all of us who
have come to the powers and responsibilities of manhood.
For did not Christ set a little child in the midst of the disciples, saying
to them that the angels of such little ones always behold the face of his
Father; saying to them that it were better for a man to hang a millstone
about his neck and plunge into the uttermost depths of the sea than to injure
such a little one?
And what today is the result of private property in land in the richest
of so-called Christian countries? Is it not that young people fear to marry;
that married people fear to have children; that children are driven out of
life from sheer want of proper nourishment and care, or compelled to toil
when they ought to be at school or at play; that great numbers of those who
attain maturity enter it with under-nourished bodies, overstrained nerves,
undeveloped minds — under conditions that foredoom them, not merely
to suffering, but to crime; that fit them in advance for the prison and the
brothel?
If your Holiness will consider these things we are confident that instead
of defending private property in land you will condemn it with anathema!
...
And it is because that in what we propose — the securing to all men
of equal natural opportunities for the exercise of their powers and the removal
of all legal restriction on the legitimate exercise of those powers — we
see the conformation of human law to the moral law, that we hold with confidence
that this is not merely the sufficient remedy for all the evils you so strikingly
portray, but that it is the only possible remedy.
Nor is there any other. The organization of man is such, his relations to
the world in which he is placed are such — that is to say, the immutable
laws of God are such, that it is beyond the power of human ingenuity to devise
any way by which the evils born of the injustice that robs men of their birthright
can be removed otherwise than by doing justice, by opening to all the bounty
that God has provided for all.
Since man can live only on land and from land, since land is the reservoir
of matter and force from which man’s body itself is taken, and on which
he must draw for all that he can produce, does it not irresistibly follow
that to give the land in ownership to some men and to deny to others all
right to it is to divide mankind into the rich and the poor, the privileged
and the helpless? Does it not follow that those who have no rights to the
use of land can live only by selling their power to labor to those who own
the land? Does it not follow that what the socialists call “the iron
law of wages,” what the political economists term “the tendency
of wages to a minimum,” must take from the landless masses — the
mere laborers, who of themselves have no power to use their labor — all
the benefits of any possible advance or improvement that does not alter this
unjust division of land? For having no power to employ themselves, they must,
either as labor-sellers or as land-renters, compete with one another for
permission to labor. This competition with one another of men shut out from
God’s inexhaustible storehouse has no limit but starvation, and must
ultimately force wages to their lowest point, the point at which life can
just be maintained and reproduction carried on. ...
The explanation of this and of similar paradoxes that in our time perplex
on every side may be easily seen. The effect of all inventions and improvements
that increase productive power, that save waste and economize effort, is
to lessen the labor required for a given result, and thus to save labor,
so that we speak of them as labor-saving inventions or improvements. Now,
in a natural state of society where the rights of all to the use of the earth
are acknowledged, labor-saving improvements might go to the very utmost that
can be imagined without lessening the demand for men, since in such natural
conditions the demand for men lies in their own enjoyment of life and the
strong instincts that the Creator has implanted in the human breast. But
in that unnatural state of society where the masses of men are disinherited
of all but the power to labor when opportunity to labor is given them by
others, there the demand for them becomes simply the demand for their services
by those who hold this opportunity, and man himself becomes a commodity.
Hence, although the natural effect of labor-saving improvement is to increase
wages, yet in the unnatural condition which private ownership of the land
begets, the effect, even of such moral improvements as the disbandment of
armies and the saving of the labor that vice entails, is, by lessening the
commercial demand, to lower wages and reduce mere laborers to starvation
or pauperism. If labor-saving inventions and improvements could be carried
to the very abolition of the necessity for labor, what would be the result?
Would it not be that landowners could then get all the wealth that the land
was capable of producing, and would have no need at all for laborers, who
must then either starve or live as pensioners on the bounty of the landowners?
Thus, so long as private property in land continues — so long as some
men are treated as owners of the earth and other men can live on it only
by their sufferance — human wisdom can devise no means by which the
evils of our present condition may be avoided.
Nor yet could the wisdom of God.
By the light of that right reason of which St. Thomas speaks we may see
that even he, the Almighty, so long as his laws remain what they are, could
do nothing to prevent poverty and starvation while property in land continues.
How could he? Should he infuse new vigor into the sunlight, new virtue into
the air, new fertility into the soil, would not all this new bounty go to
the owners of the land, and work not benefit, but rather injury, to mere
laborers? Should he open the minds of men to the possibilities of new substances,
new adjustments, new powers, could this do any more to relieve poverty than
steam, electricity and all the numberless discoveries and inventions of our
time have done? Or, if he were to send down from the heavens above
or cause to gush up from the subterranean depths, food, clothing, all the
things that
satisfy man’s material desires, to whom under our laws would all these
belong? So far from benefiting man, would not this increase and
extension of his bounty prove but a curse, enabling the privileged class
more riotously
to roll in wealth, and bringing the disinherited class to more wide-spread
starvation or pauperism. ...
In the Encyclical however you commend the application to the ordinary relations
of life, under normal conditions, of principles that in ethics are only to
be tolerated under extraordinary conditions. You are driven to this assertion
of false rights by your denial of true rights. The natural right
which each man has is not that of demanding employment or wages from another
man; but
that of employing himself — that of applying by his own labor to the
inexhaustible storehouse which the Creator has in the land provided for all
men. Were that storehouse open, as by the single tax we would open it, the
natural demand for labor would keep pace with the supply, the man who sold
labor and the man who bought it would become free exchangers for mutual advantage,
and all cause for dispute between workman and employer would be gone. For
then, all being free to employ themselves, the mere opportunity to labor
would cease to seem a boon; and since no one would work for another for less,
all things considered, than he could earn by working for himself, wages would
necessarily rise to their full value, and the relations of workman and employer
be regulated by mutual interest and convenience.
This is the only way in which they can be satisfactorily regulated.
Your Holiness seems to assume that there is some just rate of wages that
employers ought to be willing to pay and that laborers should be content
to receive, and to imagine that if this were secured there would be an end
of strife. This rate you evidently think of as that which will give working-men
a frugal living, and perhaps enable them by hard work and strict economy
to lay by a little something.
But how can a just rate of wages be fixed without the “higgling of
the market” any more than the just price of corn or pigs or ships or
paintings can be so fixed? And would not arbitrary regulation in the one
case as in the other check that interplay that most effectively promotes
the economical adjustment of productive forces? Why should buyers of labor,
any more than buyers of commodities, be called on to pay higher prices than
in a free market they are compelled to pay? Why should the sellers of labor
be content with anything less than in a free market they can obtain? Why
should working-men be content with frugal fare when the world is so rich?
Why should they be satisfied with a lifetime of toil and stinting, when the
world is so beautiful? Why should not they also desire to gratify the higher
instincts, the finer tastes? Why should they be forever content to travel
in the steerage when others find the cabin more enjoyable? ...
And thus that pseudo-charity that discards and denies justice works
evil. On the one side, it demoralizes its recipients, outraging that human
dignity
which as you say “God himself treats with reverence,” and turning
into beggars and paupers men who to become self-supporting, self-respecting
citizens need only the restitution of what God has given them. On the other
side, it acts as an anodyne to the consciences of those who are living on
the robbery of their fellows, and fosters that moral delusion and spiritual
pride that Christ doubtless had in mind when he said it was easier for a
camel to pass through the eye of a needle than for a rich man to enter the
Kingdom of Heaven. For it leads men steeped in injustice, and using their
money and their influence to bolster up injustice, to think that in giving
alms they are doing something more than their duty toward man and deserve
to be very well thought of by God, and in a vague way to attribute to their
own goodness what really belongs to God’s goodness. For consider: Who
is the All-Provider? Who is it that as you say, “owes to man a storehouse
that shall never fail,” and which “he finds only in the inexhaustible
fertility of the earth.” Is it not God? And when, therefore, men, deprived
of the bounty of their God, are made dependent on the bounty of their fellow-creatures,
are not these creatures, as it were, put in the place of God, to take credit
to themselves for paying obligations that you yourself say God owes?... read the whole letter
Rev. A. C. Auchmuty: Gems from George, a
themed collection of
excerpts from the writings of Henry George (with links to sources)
IF we are all here by the equal permission of the Creator, we are all
here with an equal title to the enjoyment of His bounty — with an equal
right to the use of all that nature so impartially offers. This is a right
which is natural and inalienable; it is a right which vests in every human
being as he enters the world, and which, during his continuance in the world,
can be limited only by the equal rights of others. There is in nature no such
thing as a fee simple in land. There is on earth no power which can rightfully
make a grant of exclusive ownership in land. If all existing men were to unite
to grant away their equal rights, they could not grant away the right of those
who follow them. For what are we but tenants for a day? Have we made the earth
that we should determine the rights of those who after us shall tenant it in
their turn? The Almighty, who created the earth for man and man for the earth,
has entailed it upon all the generations of the children of men by a decree
written upon the constitution of all things — a decree which no human
action can bar and no prescription determine, Let the parchments be ever so
many, or possession ever so long, natural justice can recognize no right in
one man to the possession and enjoyment of land that is not equally the right
of all his fellows. — Progress & Poverty — Book
VII, Chapter 1, Justice of the Remedy: Injustice of private property in land
HAS the first comer at a banquet the right to turn back all the chairs
and claim that none of the other guests shall partake of the food provided,
except as they make terms with him? Does the first man who presents a ticket
at the door of a theater and passes in, acquire by his priority the right
to shut the doors and have the performance go on for him alone? Does the
first passenger who enters a railroad car obtain the right to scatter his
baggage over all the seats and compel the passengers who come in after him
to stand up?
The cases are perfectly analogous. We arrive and we depart, guests at a banquet
continually spread, spectators and participants in an entertainment where there
is room for all who come; passengers from station to station, on an orb that
whirls through space — our rights to take and possess cannot be exclusive;
they must be bounded everywhere by the equal rights of others. Just as the
passenger in a railroad car may spread himself and his baggage over as many
seats as he pleases, until other passengers come in, so may a settler take
and use as much land as he chooses, until it is needed by others — a
fact which is shown by the land acquiring a value — when his right must
be curtailed by the equal rights of the others, and no priority of appropriation
can give a right which will bar these equal rights of others. — Progress & Poverty — Book
VII, Chapter 1, Justice of the Remedy: Injustice of private property in land
... go to "Gems from George"
Weld Carter: A Clarion Call to Sanity, to Honesty, to
Justice (1982)
Our problem today, as yesterday,
and the days before, back to the
earliest recorded times, is POVERTY. ...
... Let us begin this study of the likely causes of our troubles by
asking two questions:
- Are we over-populated?
- Are the earth's
resources inadequate for this population?
Our stage, of course, for
making this study will be this world of ours, for it is upon this
world that the drama of human living is played out, with all its joys
and all its sorrows, with all its great achievements and all its
failures, with all its nobilities and all its wickedness.
Regardless of its size relative to
other planets, with its
circumference of about twenty-five thousand miles, to any mere mortal
who must walk to the station and back each day, it is huge. Roughly
ninety-six million miles separate the sun from the earth on the
latter's eliptical journey around the sun. At this distance, the
earth makes its annual journey in its elliptical curve and it spins
on its own canted axis. Because of this cant, the sun's rays are
distributed far more evenly, thus minimizing their damage and
maximizing their benefits.
Consider the complementarity of
nature in the case of the two
forms of life we call vegetable and animal, in their respective uses
of the two gases, oxygen and carbon dioxide, the waste product of
each serving as the life-giving force of the other. Any increase in
the one will encourage a like response in the other.
Marvel at the manner in which
nature, with no help from man or
beast, delivers pure water to the highest lands, increasing it as to
their elevation, thus affording us a free ride downstream and free
power as we desire it. Look with awe at the variety and quantity of
minerals with which this world is blessed, and finally at the
fecundity nature has bestowed so lavishly throughout both animal and
vegetable life: Take note of the number of corn kernels from a single
stalk that can be grown next year from a single kernel of this year's
crop; then think of the vastly greater yields from a single cherry
pit or the seeds of a single apple, or grape or watermelon; or,
turning to the animal world, consider the hen who averages almost an
egg a day and the spawning fish as examples of the prolificacy that
is evident throughout the whole of the animal world, including
mankind.
If this marvelous earth is as rich
in resources as portrayed in
the foregoing paragraph, then the problem must be one of
distribution:
- how is the land distributed among the earth's
inhabitants, and
- how are its products in turn distributed?
Land is universally treated as
either public property or private
property. Wars are fought over land. Nowhere is it treated as common
property.
George has described this world as
a "well-provisioned ship" and
when one considers the increasingly huge daily withdrawals of such
provisions as coal and petroleum as have occurred say over the past
one hundred years, one must but agree with this writer. But this is
only a static view. Consider the suggestion of some ten years ago
that it would require the conversion of less than 20% the of the
current annual growth of wood into alcohol to fuel all the motors
then being fueled by the then-conventional means. The dynamic picture
of the future is indeed awesome, and there is every indication that
that characteristic has the potential of endless expansion. So how
is it that on so richly endowed a Garden of Eden as this world of
ours we have only been able to make of it a hell on earth for vast
numbers of people?
The answers are simple: we have
permitted, nay we have even more
than that, encouraged, the gross misallocation of resources and a
viciously wicked distribution of wealth, and we choose to be governed
by those whom we, in our ignorance, have elected. ... read
the whole essay
Rev. A. C. Auchmuty: Gems from George, a
themed collection of excerpts from the writings of Henry George (with
links to sources)
THAT man cannot exhaust or lessen the powers of nature follows from the
indestructibility of matter and the persistence of force. Production and
consumption are only relative terms. Speaking absolutely, man neither produces
nor consumes. The whole human race, were they to labor to infinity, could
not make this rolling sphere one atom heavier or one atom lighter, could
not add to or diminish by one iota the sum of the forces whose everlasting
circling produces all motion and sustains all life. As the water that we
take from the ocean must again return to the ocean, so the food we take from
the reservoirs of nature is, from the moment we take it, on its way back
to those reservoirs. What we draw from a limited extent of land may temporarily
reduce the productiveness of that land, because the return may be to other
land, or may be divided between that land and other land, or perhaps, all
land ; but this possibility lessens with increasing area, and ceases when
the whole globe is considered. — Progress & Poverty — Book
II, Chapter 3: Population and Subsistence: Inferences from Analogy
LIFE does not use up the forces that maintain life. We come into the material
universe bringing nothing; we take nothing away when we depart. The human
being, physically considered, is but a transient form of matter, a changing
mode of motion. The matter remains and the force persists. Nothing is lessened,
nothing is weakened. And from this it follows that the limit to the population
of the globe can only be the limit of space. — Progress & Poverty — Book
II, Chapter 3: Population and Subsistence: Inferences from Analogy
I BELIEVE that in a really Christian community, in a society that honored,
not with the lips but with the act, the doctrines of Jesus, no one would
have occasion to worry about physical needs any more than do the lilies of
the field. There is enough and to spare. The trouble is that, in this mad
struggle, we trample in the mire what has been provided in sufficiency for
us all; trample it in the mire while we tear and rend each other. — The
Crime of Poverty
WHOSE fault is it that social conditions are such that men have to make
that terrible choice between what conscience tells them is right, and the
necessity of earning a living? I hold that it is the fault of society; that
it is the fault of us all. Pestilence is a curse. The man who would bring
cholera to this country, or the man who, having the power to prevent its
coming here, would make no effort to do so, would be guilty of a crime. Poverty
is worse than cholera; poverty kills more people than pestilence, even in
the best of times. Look at the death statistics of our cities; see where
the deaths come quickest; see where it is that the little children die like
flies — it is in the poorer quarters. And the man who looks with careless
eyes upon the ravages of this pestilence; the man who does not set himself
to stay and eradicate it, he, I say, is guilty of a crime. — The Crime
of Poverty
SOCIAL progress makes the well-being of all more and more the business of
each; it binds all closer and closer together in bonds from which none can
escape. He who observes the law and the proprieties, and cares for his family,
yet takes no interest in the general weal, and gives no thought to those
who are trodden underfoot, save now and then to bestow alms, is not a true
Christian. Nor is he a good citizen. — Social Problems — Chapter
1, the Increasing Importance of Social Questions
WE cannot safely leave politics to politicians, or political economy to
college professors. The people themselves must think, because the people
alone can act. — Social Problems — Chapter 1, the Increasing
Importance of Social Questions
NOW, why is it that men, have to work for such low wages? Because, if they
were to demand higher wages, there are plenty of unemployed men ready to
step into their places. It is this mass of unemployed men who compel that
fierce competition that drives wages down to the point of bare subsistence.
Why is it that there are men who cannot get employment? Did you ever think
what a strange thing it is that men cannot find employment? If men cannot
find an employer, why can they not employ themselves? Simply because they
are shut out from the element on which human labor can alone be exerted;
men are compelled to compete with each other for the wages of an employer,
because they have been robbed of the natural opportunities of employing themselves;
because they cannot find a piece of God's world on which to work without
paying some other human creature for the privilege. — The Crime of
Poverty
WE laud as public benefactors those who, as we say, "furnish employment." We
are constantly talking as though this "furnishing of employment," this "giving
of work" were the greatest boon that could be conferred upon society.
To listen to much that is talked and much that is written, one would think
that the cause of poverty is that there is not work enough for so many people,
and that if the Creator had made the rock harder, the soil less fertile,
iron as scarce as gold, and gold as diamonds; or if ships would sink and
cities burn down oftener, there would be less poverty, because there would
be more work to do. — Social Problems, Chapter 8 — That We All
Might Be Rich
YOU assert the right of laborers to employment and their right to receive
from their employers a certain indefinite wage. No such rights exist. No
one has a right to demand employment of another, or to demand higher wages
than the other is willing to give, or in any way to put pressure on another
to make him raise such wages against his will. There can be no better moral
justification for such demands on employers by working-men than there would
be for employers demanding that working-men shall be compelled to work for
them when they do not want to, and to accept wages lower than they are willing
to take. — The Condition of Labor, an Open Letter to Pope Leo XIII
THE natural right which each man has, is not that of demanding employment
or wages from another man, but that of employing himself — that of
applying by his own labor to the inexhaustible storehouse which the Creator
has in the land provided for all men. Were that storehouse open, as by the
single tax we would open it, the natural demand for labor would keep pace
with the supply, the man who sold labor and the man who bought it would become
free exchangers for mutual advantage, and all cause for dispute between workman
and employer would be gone. For then, all being free to employ themselves,
the mere opportunity to labor would cease to seem a boon; and since no one
would work for another for less, all things considered, than he could earn
by working for himself, wages would necessarily rise to their full value,
and the relations of workman and employer be regulated by mutual interest
and convenience. — The Condition of Labor, an Open Letter to Pope Leo
XIII
IF we are all here by the equal permission of the Creator, we are all here
with an equal title to the enjoyment of His bounty — with an equal
right to the use of all that nature so impartially offers. This is a right
which is natural and inalienable; it is a right which vests in every human
being as he enters the world, and which, during his continuance in the world,
can be limited only by the equal rights of others. There is in nature no
such thing as a fee simple in land. There is on earth no power which can
rightfully make a grant of exclusive ownership in land. If all existing men
were to unite to grant away their equal rights, they could not grant away
the right of those who follow them. For what are we but tenants for a day?
Have we made the earth that we should determine the rights of those who after
us shall tenant it in their turn? The Almighty, who created the earth for
man and man for the earth, has entailed it upon all the generations of the
children of men by a decree written upon the constitution of all things — a
decree which no human action can bar and no prescription determine, Let the
parchments be ever so many, or possession ever so long, natural justice can
recognize no right in one man to the possession and enjoyment of land that
is not equally the right of all his fellows. — Progress & Poverty — Book
VII, Chapter 1, Justice of the Remedy: Injustice of private property in land
HAS the first comer at a banquet the right to turn back all the chairs and
claim that none of the other guests shall partake of the food provided, except
as they make terms with him? Does the first man who presents a ticket at
the door of a theater and passes in, acquire by his priority the right to
shut the doors and have the performance go on for him alone? Does the first
passenger who enters a railroad car obtain the right to scatter his baggage
over all the seats and compel the passengers who come in after him to stand
up?
The cases are perfectly analogous. We arrive and we depart, guests at a
banquet continually spread, spectators and participants in an entertainment
where there is room for all who come; passengers from station to station,
on an orb that whirls through space — our rights to take and possess
cannot be exclusive; they must be bounded everywhere by the equal rights
of others. Just as the passenger in a railroad car may spread himself and
his baggage over as many seats as he pleases, until other passengers come
in, so may a settler take and use as much land as he chooses, until it is
needed by others — a fact which is shown by the land acquiring a value — when
his right must be curtailed by the equal rights of the others, and no priority
of appropriation can give a right which will bar these equal rights of others. — Progress & Poverty — Book
VII, Chapter 1, Justice of the Remedy: Injustice of private property in land
... go to "Gems from George"
|
To
share this page with a friend: right click, choose "send," and
add your comments.
|
|
Red
links have not been visited; .
Green
links are pages you've seen |
Essential Documents
pertinent to this theme:
|
|