Many of my friends pride themselves on conserving water and energy, and
endorse the idea of "living simply so that others may simply live." I
am often troubled, however, that until we get our incentives right, so that
the big users of water and energy — not to mention the big polluters — have
the incentives to behave similarly, my friends' individual efforts and sacrifice
are going to be to little effect. Similarly, I see churches, synagogues and
mosques
being encouraged to devote themselves to charitable efforts to help the poor,
rather than concentrating on seeking poverty's underlying causes and working
to eradicate the structural reasons we have such widespread poverty and misery
in a country dedicated to the proposition that all of us are created equal.
(see fences and bandages.)
We tax the wrong things — labor and capital — and tax only
lightly that which should be taxed heavily — land value. The effects
are widespread
and
serious, and until we correct these distortions, we can't expect our efforts
to reduce poverty or sprawl to do more than provide palliative care.
Incentive Taxation is another term
often used for Land Value Taxation,
Site Value Taxation and Split-Rate Taxation. It aligns the
incentives with the ideals we hold dear, ideals such as equality and equality
of opportunity!
Charles B. Fillebrown: A Catechism
of Natural Taxation, from Principles of
Natural Taxation (1917)
Q50. How could the landowner escape the alleged burden of an increase
in his land tax?
A. Simply by assuming the legitimate role of a model landlord, by putting his
land to suitable use, in providing for tenants at lowest possible price the best
accommodations and facilities appropriate to the situation that money can buy.
... read the whole article
Henry George: The Common Sense of Taxation (1881
article)
Evidently this regard for the general good is the true principle of taxation.
The more it is examined the more clearly it will be seen that there is
no valid reason why we should, in any case, attempt to tax all property.
That equality should be the rule and aim of taxation is true, and this
for the reason given in the Declaration of Independence, that all men are
created equal. But equality does not require that all men should be taxed
alike, or that all things should be taxed alike. It merely requires that
whatever taxes are imposed shall be equally imposed upon the persons or
things in like conditions or situations; it merely requires that no citizen
shall be given an advantage, or put at a disadvantage, as compared with
other citizens.
The true purposes of government are well stated in the preamble to the Constitution
of the United States, as they are in the Declaration of Independence. To
insure the general peace, to promote the general welfare, to secure to each
individual the inalienable rights to life, liberty, and the pursuit of happiness — these
are the proper ends of government, and are therefore the ends which in every
scheme of taxation should be kept in mind. ...
But while no limit can be properly fixed for the amount of taxation, the
method of taxation is of supreme importance. A horse may be anchored by fastening
to his bridle a weight which he will not feel when carried in a buggy behind
him. The best ship may be made utterly unseaworthy by the bad stowage of
a cargo which properly placed would make her the stiffer and more weatherly.
So enterprise may be palsied, industry crushed, accumulation prevented, and
a prosperous country turned into a desert, by taxation which rightly levied
would hardly be felt. ...
Nothing is clearer than that when a farmer who wants more capital puts a
mortgage on his farm, no new value is thereby created. Yet, in most of our
States, both the farm and the mortgage are taxed; though so obvious is the
double taxation that in some of them the clumsy expedient of making an exemption
to the debtor is resorted to.
But it is manifest that property of this kind is not a fit subject for taxation,
and ought not to be considered in making up the assessment rolls. It has,
in itself, no value. It is merely the representative, or token, of value — the
certificate of ownership, or the obligation to pay value. It either represents
other property, or property yet to be brought into existence. And, as nothing
real can be drawn from that which is not real, taxation upon property of
this kind must ultimately fall, either upon the property represented, in
which case there is double taxation, or upon those whose obligations it expresses,
in which case men are taxed, not upon what they own, but upon what they owe;
and all cumbrous devices to prevent the unjust effects of such taxation,
like other complications of the revenue system, simply give to the stronger
and more unscrupulous opportunities of throwing the burden upon the weaker
and more conscientious. Property of this kind ought not to be taxed at all.
Property in itself valuable is clearly that with which any wise scheme of
taxation should alone deal.
To consider the nature of property of this kind is again to see a clear
distinction. That distinction is not, as the lawyers have it, between movables
and immovables, between personal property and real estate. The true distinction
is between property which is, and property which is not, the result of human
labor; or, to use the terms of political economy, between land and wealth.
For, in any precise use of the term, land is not wealth, any more than labor
is wealth. Land and labor are the factors of production. Wealth is such result
of their union as retains the capacity of ministering to human desire. A
lot and the house which stands upon it are alike property, alike have a tangible
value, and are alike classed as real estate. But there are between them the
most essential differences. The one is the free gift of Nature, the other
the result of human exertion; the one exists from generation to generation,
while men come and go; the other is constantly tending to decay, and can
only be preserved by continual exertion. To the one, the right of exclusive
possession, which makes it individual property, can, like the right of property
in slaves, be traced to nothing but municipal law; to the other, the right
of exclusive property springs clearly from those natural relations which
are among the primary perceptions of the human mind. Nor are these mere abstract
distinctions. They are distinctions of the first importance in determining
what should and what should not be taxed.
For, keeping in mind the fact that all wealth is the result of human exertion,
it is clearly seen that, having in view the promotion of the general prosperity,
it is the height of absurdity to tax wealth for purposes of revenue while
there remains, unexhausted by taxation, any value attaching to land. We may
tax land values as much as we please, without in the slightest degree lessening
the amount of land, or the capabilities of land, or the inducement to use
land. But we cannot tax wealth without lessening the inducement to the production
of wealth, and decreasing the amount of wealth. We might take the whole value
of land in taxation, so as to make the ownership of land worth nothing, and
the land would still remain, and be as useful as before. The effect would
be to throw land open to users free of price, and thus to increase its capabilities,
which are brought out by increased population. But impose anything like such
taxation upon wealth, and the inducement to the production of wealth would
be gone. Movable wealth would be hidden or carried off, immovable wealth
would be suffered to go to decay, and where was prosperity would soon be
the silence of desolation.
And the reason of this difference is clear. The possession of wealth is
the inducement to the exertion necessary to the production and maintenance
of wealth. Men do not work for the pleasure of working, but to get the things
their work will give them. And to tax the things that are produced by exertion
is to lessen the inducement to exertion. But over and above the benefit to
the possessor, which is the stimulating motive to the production of wealth,
there is a benefit to the community, for no matter how selfish he may be,
it is utterly impossible for any one to entirely keep to himself the benefit
of any desirable thing he may possess. These diffused benefits when localized
give value to land, and this may be taxed without in any wise diminishing
the incentive to production.
To illustrate: A man builds a fine house or large factory in a poorly improved
neighborhood. To tax this building and its adjuncts is to make him pay for
his enterprise and expenditure — to take from him part of his natural
reward. But the improvement thus made has given new beauty or life to the
neighborhood, making it a more desirable place than before for the erection
of other houses or factories, and additional value is given to land all about.
Now to tax improvements is not only to deprive of his proper reward the man
who has made the improvement, but it is to deter others from making similar
improvements. But, instead of taxing improvements, to tax these land values
is to leave the natural inducement to further improvement in full force,
and at the same time to keep down an obstacle to further improvement, which,
under the present system, improvement itself tends to raise. For the advance
of land values which follows improvement, and even the expectation of improvement,
makes further improvement more costly.
See how unjust and short-sighted is this system. Here is a man who, gathering
what little capital he can, and taking his family, starts West to find a
place where he can make himself a home. He must travel long distances; for,
though he will pass plenty of land nobody is using, it is held at prices
too high for him. Finally he will go no further, and selects a place where,
since the creation of the world, the soil, so far as we know, has never felt
a plowshare. But here, too, in nine cases out of ten, he will find the speculator
has been ahead of him, for the speculator moves quicker, and has superior
means of information to the emigrant. Before he can put this land to the
use for which nature intended it, and to which it is for the general good
that it should be put, he must make terms with some man who in all probability
never saw the land, and never dreamed of using it, and who, it may be, resides
in some city, thousands of miles away. In order to get permission to use
this land, he must give up a large part of the little capital which is seed-wheat
to him, and perhaps in addition mortgage his future labor for years. Still
he goes to work: he works himself, and his wife works, and his children work — work
like horses, and live in the hardest and dreariest manner. Such a man deserves
encouragement, not discouragement; but on him taxation falls with peculiar
severity. Almost everything that he has to buy — groceries, clothing,
tools — is largely raised in price by a system of tariff taxation which
cannot add to the price of the grain or hogs or cattle that he has to sell.
And when the assessor comes around he is taxed on the improvements he has
made, although these improvements have added not only to the value of surrounding
land, but even to the value of land in distant commercial centers. Not merely
this, but, as a general rule, his land, irrespective of the improvements,
will be assessed at a higher rate than unimproved land around it, on the
ground that "productive property" ought to pay more than "unproductive
property" — a principle just the reverse of the correct one, for
the man who makes land productive adds to the general prosperity, while the
man who keeps land unproductive stands in the way of the general prosperity,
is but a dog-in-the-manger, who prevents others from using what he will not
use himself.
Or, take the case of the railroads. That railroads are a public benefit
no one will dispute. We want more railroads, and want them to reduce their
fares and freight. Why then should we tax them? for taxes upon railroads
deter from railroad building, and compel higher charges. Instead of taxing
the railroads, is it not clear that we should rather tax the increased value
which they give to land? To tax railroads is to check railroad building,
to reduce profits, and compel higher rates; to tax the value they give to
land is to increase railroad business and permit lower rates. The elevated
railroads, for instance, have opened to the overcrowded population of New
York the wide, vacant spaces of the upper part of the island. But this great
public benefit is neutralized by the rise in land values. Because these vacant
lots can be reached more cheaply and quickly, their owners demand more for
them, and so the public gain in one way is offset in another, while the roads
lose the business they would get were not building checked by the high prices
demanded for lots. The increase of land values, which the elevated roads
have caused, is not merely no advantage to them — it is an injury;
and it is clearly a public injury. The elevated railroads ought not to be
taxed. The more profit they make, with the better conscience can they be
asked to still further reduce fares. It is the increased land values which
they have created that ought to be taxed, for taxing them will give the public
the full benefit of cheap fares.
So with railroads everywhere. And so not alone with railroads, but with
all industrial enterprises. So long as we consider that community most prosperous
which increases most rapidly in wealth, so long is it the height of absurdity
for us to tax wealth in any of its beneficial forms. We should tax what we
want to repress, not what we want to encourage. We should tax that which
results from the general prosperity, not that which conduces to it. It is
the increase of population, the extension of cultivation, the manufacture
of goods, the building of houses and ships and railroads, the accumulation
of capital, and the growth of commerce that add to the value of land — not
the increase in the value of land that induces the increase of population
and increase of wealth. It is not that the land of Manhattan Island is now
worth hundreds of millions where, in the time of the early Dutch settlers,
it was only worth dollars, that there are on it now so many more people,
and so much more wealth. It is because of the increase of population and
the increase of wealth that the value of the land has so much increased.
Increase of land values tends of itself to repel population and prevent improvement.
And thus the taxation of land values, unlike taxation of other property,
does not tend to prevent the increase of wealth, but rather to stimulate
it. It is the taking of the golden egg, not the choking of the goose that
lays it.
Every consideration of policy and ethics squares with this conclusion. The
tax upon land values is the most economically perfect of all taxes. It does
not raise prices; it maybe collected at least cost, and with the utmost ease
and certainty; it leaves in full strength all the springs of production;
and, above all, it consorts with the truest equality and the highest justice.
For, to take for the common purposes of the community that value which results
from the growth of the community, and to free industry and enterprise and
thrift from burden and restraint, is to leave to each that which he fairly
earns, and to assert the first and most comprehensive of equal rights — the
equal right of all to the land on which, and from which, all must live.
Thus it is that the scheme of taxation which conduces to the greatest production
is also that which conduces to the fairest distribution, and that in the
proper adjustment of taxation lies not merely the possibility of enormously
increasing the general wealth, but the solution of these pressing social
and political problems which spring from unnatural inequality in the distribution
of wealth.
"There is," says M. de Laveleye, in concluding that work in which
he shows that the first perceptions of mankind have everywhere recognized
a most vital distinction between property in land and property which results
from labor, — "there is in human affairs one system which is the
best; it is not that system which always exists, otherwise why should we
desire to change it; but it is that system which should exist for the greatest
good of humanity. God knows it, and wills it; man's duty it is to discover
and establish it." ... read the
whole article
H.G. Brown: Significant
Paragraphs from Henry George's Progress & Poverty:
10. Effect of Remedy Upon Wealth Production (in the unabridged P&P: Part
IX — Effects of the Remedy: Chapter 1 — Of the effect upon
the production of wealth)
...Well may the community leave to the individual producer all that prompts
him to exertion; well may it let the laborer have the full reward of his labor,
and the capitalist the full return of his capital. For the more that labor
and capital produce, the greater grows the common wealth in which all may share.
And in the value or rent of land is this general gain expressed in a definite
and concrete form. Here is a fund which the state may take while leaving to
labor and capital their full reward. With increased activity of production
this would commensurately increase.
And to shift the burden of taxation from production and exchange to the value
or rent of land would not merely be to give new stimulus to the production
of wealth; it would be to open new opportunities. For under this system no
one would care to hold land unless to use it, and land now withheld from use
would everywhere be thrown open to improvement.
The selling price of land would fall; land speculation would receive its death
blow; land monopolization would no longer pay.* Millions and millions of acres
from which settlers are now shut out by high prices would be abandoned by their
present owners or sold to settlers upon nominal terms. And this not merely
on the frontiers, but within what are now considered well settled districts.
* The fact that a tax on the rental value of land cannot
be shifted by landowners to tenants, though recognized by all competent
economists, is sometimes a stumbling block to persons untrained in economics.
The reason such a tax cannot be shifted is that it cannot limit the supply
of land. Landowners are presumably, before the tax is laid, charging all
the rent they can get. There is nothing in a tax on the rental value of
land to make tenants willing to pay more or to make land more difficult
to hire. On the contrary, more land will be on the market, because of such
a tax, rather than less, since the tax puts a heavy penalty on holding
land out of use and unimproved for mere speculation. The competition of
former vacant land speculators to get their land used will make land cheaper
to rent rather than more expensive. And since only the net rent remaining
after the tax is subtracted is capitalized into salable value, land will
be very much cheaper to buy. H.G.B.
And it must be remembered that this would apply, not merely to agricultural
land, but to all land. Mineral land would be thrown open to use, just as agricultural
land; and in the heart of a city no one could afford to keep land from its
most profitable use, or on the outskirts to demand more for it than the use
to which it could at the time be put would warrant. Everywhere that land had
attained a value, taxation, instead of operating, as now, as a fine upon improvement,
would operate to force improvement. Whoever planted an orchard, or sowed a
field, or built a house, or erected a manufactory, no matter how costly, would
have no more to pay in taxes than if he kept so much land idle.
- The monopolist of agricultural land would be taxed as much as though
his land were covered with houses and barns, with crops and with stock.
- The owner of a vacant city lot would have to pay as much for the privilege
of keeping other people off of it until he wanted to use it, as his
neighbor who has a fine house upon his lot.
- It would cost as much to keep a row of tumble-down shanties upon valuable
land as though it were covered with a grand hotel or a pile of great
warehouses filled with costly goods.
Thus, the bonus that wherever labor is most productive must now be paid before
labor can be exerted would disappear.
- The farmer would not have to pay out half his means, or mortgage his
labor for years, in order to obtain land to cultivate;
- the builder of a city homestead would not have to lay out as much for
a small lot as for the house he puts upon it*;
- the company that proposed to erect a manufactory would not have to expend
a great part of its capital for a site.
- And what would be paid from year to year to the state would be in lieu
of all the taxes now levied upon improvements, machinery, and stock.
*Many persons, and among them some professional economists,
have never succeeded in getting a thorough comprehension of this point.
Thus, the editor has heard the objection advanced that the greater
cheapness of land is no advantage to the poor man who is trying to
save enough from his earnings to buy a piece of land; for, it is said,
the higher taxes on the land after it is acquired, offset the lower
purchase price. What such objectors do not see is that even if the
lower price of land does no more than balance the higher tax on it,
(and this overlooks, for one thing, the discouragement to speculation
in land), the reduction or removal of other taxes is all clear gain.
It is easier to save in proportion as earnings and commodities are
relieved of taxation. It is easier to buy land, because its selling
price is lower, if the land is taxed. And although the land, after
its purchase, continues to be taxed, not only can this tax be fully
paid out of the annual interest on the saving in the purchase price,
but also there is to be reckoned the saving in taxes on buildings and
other improvements and in whatever other taxes are thus rendered unnecessary.
H.G.B.
Consider the effect of such a change upon the labor market. Competition
would no longer be one-sided, as now. Instead of laborers competing with
each other
for employment, and in their competition cutting down wages to the point
of bare subsistence, employers would everywhere be competing for laborers,
and
wages would rise to the fair earnings of labor. For into the labor market
would have entered the greatest of all competitors for the employment of
labor, a
competitor whose demand cannot be satisfied until want is satisfied — the
demand of labor itself. The employers of labor would not have merely to
bid against other employers, all feeling the stimulus of greater trade
and increased
profits, but against the ability of laborers to become their own employers
upon the natural opportunities freely opened to them by the tax which prevented
monopolization.
With natural opportunities thus free to labor;
- with capital and improvements exempt from tax, and exchange released
from restrictions, the spectacle of willing men unable to turn their labor
into
the things they are suffering for would become impossible;
- the recurring paroxysms which paralyze industry would cease;
- every wheel of production would be set in motion;
- demand would keep pace with supply, and supply with demand;
- trade would increase in every direction, and wealth augment on every
hand. ... read the whole chapter
Louis Post: Outlines of Louis F. Post's
Lectures, with Illustrative Notes and Charts (1894)
f. The Single Tax Retains Rent for Common Use.
To retain Rent for common use it is not necessary to abolish land-titles,
nor to let land out to the highest bidder, nor to invent some new mechanism
of taxation, nor in any other way to directly change existing modes of holding
land for use, or existing machinery for collecting public revenues. "Great
changes can be best brought about under old forms."109 Let land be held
nominally as it is now. Let taxes be collected by the same kind of machinery
as now. But abolish all taxes except those that fall upon actual and potential
Rent, that is to say, upon land values.
If that were done it is doubtful if land-owners could any longer confiscate
enough Rent to be worth the trouble. Even though some surplus were
still kept by them, it would be so much more easy to secure Wealth by working
for
it than by confiscating Rent to private use, to say nothing of its being
so much more respectable, that speculation in land values would practically
be abandoned. At any rate, the question of a surplus — Rent in excess
of the requirements of the community — may be readily determined
when the principle that Rent justly belongs to the community and Wages
to the
individual shall have been recognized by society in the adoption of the
Single Tax. 110
110. Thomas G. Shearman, Esq., of New York, author of
the famous magazine article on "Who Owns the United States," estimates
that sixty-five per cent of the present annual value of the land in the
United States would pay all the present expenses of American government — federal,
state, county, and municipal. ... read the book
Nic Tideman: Basic Tenets of the
Incentive Taxation Philosophy
Alanna Hartzok: Earth
Rights Democracy: Public Finance based on Early Christian Teachings
Mason Gaffney: The Taxable
Capacity of Land
The question I am
assigned is whether the taxable
capacity of land without buildings is up to the job of financing
cities, counties, and schools. Will the revenue be enough? The answer
is "yes."
The universal state and
local revenue problem today is
whether we must cap tax rates to avoid driving business away. It is
exemplified by Governor Pete Wilson of the suffering State of
California. He keeps repeating we
must make a hard choice: cut taxes
and public services, or drive out business and jobs. (When a public
figure gives you two choices you know they're both bad, and he wants
one of them.)
The unique, remarkable quality of
a property tax based on
land ex buildings is that you may raise the rate with no fear of
driving away business, construction, people, jobs, or capital! You
certainly will not drive away the land. However high the tax
rate,
not one square foot of it will put on a track shoe and hop out of
town. The only bad thing to say about this tax's incentive effects is
that it stimulates revitalization, and makes jobs. If some people
think that is bad, maybe this attitude is the problem. ... Read the
whole article
Ted Gwartney: A Free Market Strategy to
Reduce Sprawl
One means that has long been available but not brought into general use is
to exempt buildings from the real estate tax and begin to impose an annual
tax on land sites that makes holding land off the market for speculation a
costly proposition. An annual fee on land should be set near what the land
site alone would yield if rented by the owner to the highest bidder. Think
of how this would change the behavior of land owners. If I owned a parcel of
land with a rental value of $6,000 a year and that was near what the city charged
me as my annual fee, my return on investment as a land speculator would be
greatly reduced. In order to generate positive cash flow I would either develop
the land myself or put it on the market so that someone else would develop
it. At the same time, if my tax rate on the building I constructed on the land
was zero, my incentive is to construct a building that maximizes my cash flow
(i.e., to develop the parcel to its highest and best use in the market). At
minimum, land prices would stabilize and the increase in land brought onto
the market would be somewhat offset by increased demand. Land prices to builders
would tend to begin to fall over time. ... read
the whole article
Nic Tideman: The Case
for Taxing Land
I. Taxing Land as Ethics
and Efficiency
II. What is Land?
III. The simple efficiency argument for taxing land
IV. Taxing Land is Better Than Neutral
V. Measuring the Economic Gains from Shifting Taxes to Land
VI. The Ethical Case for Taxing Land
VII. Answer to Arguments against Taxing Land
There is a case for taxing land based on ethical principles and
a case
for taxing land based on efficiency principles. As a matter of
logic, these two cases are separate. Ethical conclusions
follow from ethical premises and efficiency conclusions from efficiency
principles. However, it is natural for human minds to conflate
the two cases. It is easier to believe that something is good if
one knows that it is efficient, and it is easier to see that something
is efficient if one believes that it is good. Therefore it is
important for a discussion of land taxation to address both question of
efficiency and questions of ethics.
This monograph will first address the efficiency case for taxing land,
because that is the less controversial case. The efficiency case
for taxing land has two main parts. ...
To estimate the magnitudes of the impacts that additional taxes
on land
would have on an economy, one must have a model of the economy. I
report on estimates of the magnitudes of impacts on the U.S. economy of
shifting taxes to land, based on a mathematical model that is outlined
in the Appendix.
The ethical case for
taxing land is based on two ethical premises: ...
The ethical case for taxing land ends with a discussion of the
reasons
why recognition of the equal rights of all to land may be essential for
world peace.
After developing the efficiency argument and the ethical
argument for
taxing land, I consider a variety of counter-arguments that have been
offered against taxing land. For a given level of other taxes, a
rise in the rate at which land is taxed causes a fall in the selling
price of land. It is sometimes argued that only modest taxes on
land are therefore feasible, because as the rate of taxation on land
increases and the selling price of land falls, market transactions
become increasingly less reliable as indicators of the value of
land. ...
Another basis on which it is argued that greatly increased taxes
on
land are infeasible is that if land values were to fall precipitously,
the financial system would collapse. ...
Apart from questions of feasibility, it is sometimes argued that
erosion of land values from taxing land would harm economic efficiency,
because it would reduce opportunities for entrepreneurs to use land as
collateral for loans to finance their ideas. ...
.
Another ethical argument that is made against taxing land is
that the
return to unusual ability is “rent” just as the return to land is
rent. ...
But before developing any of these arguments, I must discuss
what land
is. ...
What makes it impossible to tax everything at the same rate is
that one
of the things that would need to be taxed is leisure. Taxing
authorities have not yet devised ways to maintain people’s tax
obligations when they decide to earn and spend less money. Thus
all systems that tax people according to what they receive (from
working or saving), or spend, generate excess burdens. They do
this by making the incentive to work less than the value of what people
produce and the incentive to save less than the productivity of
investments financed by saving. Still, systems of ‘broad-based’
taxes (e.g., sales taxes, income taxes and value added taxes) generally
have lower excess burdens than tax systems in which a variety of
individual goods and services are taxed at different rates.
Actual broad-based taxes generally have exceptions and
non-uniformities, and these generally increase the excess burdens that
the taxes cause. Still, one way in which a departure from
uniformity in taxation can promote efficiency is that, if there are
some goods and services that are particularly likely to be purchased in
greater quantity when people consume more leisure, then a somewhat
higher tax on these can serve as a partial substitute for taxing
leisure.
In addition to discouraging work, most tax systems discourage
saving by
taxing the proceeds of people’s savings. This results in less
saving and investment. With the passage of time, this can cause a
very large reduction in the amount of capital in an economy. And
a reduced stock of capital generally means that labor will be less
productive and wages will be lower. A tax system that taxed only
consumption and not saving would not have this component of excess
burden. However, raising a given amount of revenue in a tax system that
did not tax saving would require a greater distortion of the
labor/leisure decision than in a tax system that did tax saving. ...
...The supply of land is said to be perfectly
inelastic, vertical. Thus when a tax introduces a wedge between
the price paid by buyers of land services and the price received by
seller, the quantity remains unchanged. The triangle
disappears. Thus there is no excess burden of a tax on
land. A tax on land is ‘neutral’.
There are several limitations of this analysis.
- First, the tax
must not be more than the rental value of land, or no one will be
willing to hold title to land and pay the tax. Since the most
productive uses of land often require capital that is durable and
immobile, it is also necessary for people to be confident when they
contemplate investment that the tax will not exceed the rental value of
the land over the life of the investment.
- Second, the tax must be administered in such a way that
the tax will
not increase if the land is used more productively. That would
discourage productive use of the land.
- Finally, the analysis as
presented applies only to the indestructible components of land.
If there are ways that people might want to use land that would reduce
its value compared to what nature provided (as with mining or fishing),
then a tax on land in proportion to its value will give people an
inefficient incentive to reduce its value.
There is a way to eliminate this
inefficient incentive. One can
apply to mineable land a ‘severance tax’ for reductions in value.
To exactly offset the incentive effects of a land value tax, the amount
of the severance tax should be the present value of the reductions in
the land value tax that occur because of the reduction in the value of
the
land. Then the present value of the sum of the land value tax
payments and the severance tax payments will be independent of how
the land is used
To summarize: If land is subject to a tax or combination of
taxes with
a present value that is independent of how the land is used, and if
potential investors are confident that the magnitude of the tax will
not exceed the value of using the land over the life of potential
investments, then a tax on land has no excess burden; it is
neutral. ...
Because increases in land value generally cause reductions in
both the
value of location-specific human capital and the value of pre-existing
structures, an efficient system of incentives for activities that
increase land values would offer incentives reflecting only the net
benefits, after the value of the negative consequences for physical and
human capital had been subtracted from the increase in land
values. An ideal system would collect all of the extra increase
in land value and use it to provide compensation for the negative
consequences for physical and human capital. Read the
whole article
Nic Tideman: Using Tax
Policy to Promote Urban Growth
Urban growth is desired because it raises peoples' incomes.
In a
market economy, incomes can be divided into components derived from
four factors of production:
- the rent of land,
- the wages of labor,
- the interest received from owning capital, and
- the profits of entrepreneurship (the activity of choosing
investments and organizing production).
Thus a successful urban growth strategy in a market economy
must
either increase the amounts of land, labor, capital and
entrepreneurship that are used in a city or increase the payments
that are made per unit of each factor, or both.
The land that a city has is fixed (or if it changes, it does
so at
the expense of other administrative units). Therefore, with respect
to land, socially productive urban growth means adopting policies
that raise the productivity of land. Labor, on the other hand, is
reasonably mobile, and capital is highly mobile. Entrepreneurship
springs up and fades away with the rise and fall of opportunities.
Therefore, in a market economy, the payments that must be made to
attract these factors are substantially outside the control of a
city. Thus the growth of a city with respect to labor, capital and
entrepreneurship is achieved primarily by making the city a place
that attracts more of these factors, taking the rates of wages,
interest and profits that must be paid to attract them as given by
market forces.
Tax policy is critical for urban growth because taxes on the
earnings of labor, capital and entrepreneurship drive these factors
away. A city that desires to grow should refrain from taxing wages,
interest or profits and concentrate its taxes on land, which does not
have the option of moving away.
Certain other sources of public revenue, in addition to the
rent
of land, have the characteristic of not discouraging growth. These
sources of revenue involve either charging people for using scarce
opportunities that no one created, as with land, or charging people
for the costs that their actions impose on others.
A city that wishes to grow should confine its search for
revenue
to these sources. In this way it will attract more labor, capital and
entrepreneurship, thereby raising the rent of land, which can be
collected publicly without discouraging growth.
Additions to the stock of capital are extremely important for
urban growth, because of the impact of abundant capital on wages and
rents. When capital is abundant, labor and land are more productive,
and the more productive they are, the higher wages and rents are. ...
... Every activity that is
continued should pass a test of providing adequate value for money.
Most of the worthwhile activities of local governments raise the
rental value of the land in the vicinity of the activity by enough to
pay a substantial fraction if not all of the costs of the activity.
Thus the rental value of land is a natural first source of
financing for local public expenditures.
Making the rental value of land a principal source of local
public
revenue has both an equity rationale and an efficiency rationale. The
equity argument for social collection of the rent of land is founded
on a recognition that the rental value of land has three sources.
- Part of the rental value
of land is the gift of nature--the fertility
of soil, the value of good rivers and harbors, the depletable value
of minerals, and so on. This part of the rental value of land should
be collected publicly because no individual has a just claim to more
than a proportionate share of it. Public collection is just either if
it is followed by an equal distribution to all citizens or by
spending on activities that provide equal benefits to all.
- A second part of the
rental value of land comes from the provision
of public services. The local agencies that provide these
services
can justly claim the increase in the rental value of land that
results from their activities.
- A third part of the
rental value of any particular site arises
from private activities that are conducted in the vicinity of that
site. Social collection of this part of the rental value of
land is
particularly appropriate if this money is used to reward those
private activities according to how much they increase the rental
value of land.
The efficiency argument for social collection of the rent of
land
has two parts.
- First, the rental value
of land has the rare quality of being a source of public revenue that
does not discourage productive activity. If people are taxed
according to their labor earnings, they can be expected to work less,
and to tend to move from the places that tax them. If people are taxed
on their investments and savings, they can be expected to save and
invest less, and to find it attractive to put their savings and
investments in other places where they will not be taxed as much. But
when the rental value of land is collected, no one will reduce the
amount of land in existence, and no one will move his land elsewhere.
Thus social collection of the rent of land does not reduce the
productivity of an economy in the way that most other sources of public
revenue do.
- The second part of the
efficiency argument is that social collection of the rent of land tends
to make land more available to those who want to start new enterprises.
When the rent of land is
not collected publicly, those who have rights to land will tend to
ignore the possibility of releasing it to someone who might make better
use of it. On the other hand, if those who have rights to land
are required to make annual payments equal to the market value of the
rights they hold, then these continuing payments will induce people to
ask themselves regularly whether they ought to release the land to
someone who can make better use of it.
To achieve the potential efficiency of public revenue from
land,
it is important that people not be charged more for the use of land,
just because they happen to be using it particularly productively.
The rental value of land should be reassessed regularly, the values
that are determined should vary smoothly with location, and they
should be available for public inspection so that all users of land
can see that they are being charged amounts commensurate with what
their neighbors are being charged.
Social collection of the rent of land also facilitates the
privatization of land. If every user of land is charged annually
according to the rental value of the land that he or she holds, then
it is possible to undertake a just privatization of land simply by
passing out titles to the current users of land.
No one will be disadvantaged by not receiving land. Future
generations will not be deprived by not having been awarded shares.
And the community will have a continuing income from the rent of
land.
The
efficiency that is entailed in using the rent of land to
finance public activities applies to certain other sources of public
revenue as well:
1. Charges on any publicly granted privileges, such
as the exclusive right to use a portion of the frequency spectrum for
radio and TV broadcasts.
2. Payments for extractions of natural resources. Such
payments should be set at levels that yield the greatest possible
revenue of the resources, in present value terms.
3. Taxes on pollution. Every individual or enterprise that
pollutes the air, water or ground should be required to pay the
estimated cost of the pollution it generates. The effect of pollution
on the rental value of surrounding land is one possible measure of its
cost.
4. Taxes on any other activities that reduce the rental
value of surrounding land.
5. Taxes on activities such as driving or parking in
crowded streets, where one person's activities reduce opportunities for
others. The administration of such charges may be so expensive that it
is not worth implementing them, but if the administration can be
handled sufficiently cheaply, these charges are efficient to the extent
that they only charge people for costs imposed on others.
6. Taxes on activities, such as the consumption of alcohol,
which impose costs on others (e.g., higher traffic fatalities).
7. Charges for local public services, such as water,
electricity, sewer connections, etc. It is not generally desirable to
make every service completely self-financing. Rather, what is desirable
is that each user be required to pay the marginal cost of the service
he receives. Extensions of service networks are efficient when they
increase publicly collected land rents by enough to cover the costs not
covered by user charges.
8. A self-assessed tax on permanent improvements to land,
at a very low rate (perhaps 1/10 of 1% per year). With a self-assessed
tax, each possessor of land names a price at which he would be willing
to part with the land he possesses (and any immovable improvements). He
pays a tax proportional to the value he names, and anyone who wishes to
may take over possession at that price. The value of such a tax is that
it makes it much easier to assemble land for redevelopment, and to
identify appropriate compensation when land is taken for public
purposes.
All
of the above taxes are positively beneficial and should be
collected even if the revenue is not needed for public purposes. Any
excess can be returned to the population on an equal per capita
basis. If these attractive sources of revenue do not suffice to
finance necessary public expenditures, then the least damaging
additional tax would probably be a "poll tax," a uniform charge on
all residents. If some residents are regarded to be incapable of
paying such a tax, then the next most efficient tax is a proportional
tax on income up to some specified amount. Then there is no
disincentive effect for all persons who reach the tax limit. The next
most efficient tax is a proportional tax on all income.
It is important not to tax
the profits of corporations. Capital
moves from where it is taxed to where it is not, until the same rate
of return is earned everywhere. If the city refrains from taxing
corporations they will invest more in St. Petersburg. Wages will be
higher, and the rent of land, collected by the government, will be
higher. The least damaging tax on corporations is one that provides a
complete write-off of investments, with a carry-over of tax credits
to future years. Such a tax has the effect of making the government a
partner in all new investments. With such a tax the government
provides, through tax credits, the same share of costs that it later
receives in revenues. However, the tax does diminish the incentive
for entrepreneurial activity, and it raises no revenue when
investment is expanding rapidly. Furthermore, the efficiency of such
a tax requires that everyone believe that the tax rate will never
change. Thus it is best not to tax the profits of corporations at
all. If the people of St. Petersburg want to share in the profits of
corporations, then they should invest directly in the corporations,
either privately or publicly. The residents of St. Petersburg would
be best served by refraining from taxing the profits of corporations.
Creating a place where profits are not taxed can be expected to
attract so much capital that the resulting rises in wages and in
government-collected rents will more than offset what might have been
collected by taxing profits.
The taxes that promote urban growth have at least one of two
features.
- The first feature that a growth-promoting tax can have is
that it can serve to allocate a naturally occurring resource among
competing potential users. Charges for the use of land, for the use
of the frequency spectrum and for depleting natural resources share
this feature.
- The second feature that a growth-promoting tax can have
is that of being a charge for the costs imposed on the city by the
person who pays the tax. This feature is shared by taxes on
pollution, taxes on other activities that reduce the value of
surrounding land, taxes on imposing congestion and other costs on
other residents of the city, charges for the marginal cost of
publicly provided services, and a self-assessed tax on property,
reflecting the hindrance to future growth represented by existing
development.
A city that confines itself to these taxes can expect to
attract capital rapidly, and therefore to experience rapid growth,
raising the wages of its citizens and the publicly-collected rent of
its land.Read the whole article
Nic Tideman: Land Taxation and Efficient
Land Speculation
The optimal timing of development is an important allocative function that
can be either enhanced or degraded by the impact of land taxes on land
speculation. This paper discusses four types of
taxes on land:
- taxes on the rental value of land,
- taxes on the sale value of land,
- taxes on realized income from land, and
- taxes on realized gains from the sale of land.
All four taxes reduce incentives for speculation in land, which is generally
beneficial. The third and fourth produce distortions with respect to incentives
to develop land, while the first and second do not. All four taxes have some
beneficial effect of mitigating imperfections in capital markets. All permit
reduction or elimination of taxes with significant dead-weight losses, such
as those on improvements. ... read the whole article
Jeff Smith and Kris Nelson: Giving
Life to the Property Tax Shift (PTS)
John Muir is right. "Tug on any
one
thing and find it connected to everything else in the universe." Tug on
the property tax and find it connected to urban slums, farmland loss,
political favoritism, and unearned equity with disrupted neighborhood
tenure. Echoing Thoreau, the more familiar reforms have failed to
address this many-headed hydra at its root. To think that the root
could be chopped by a mere shift in the property tax base -- from
buildings to land -- must seem like the epitome of unfounded faith. Yet
the evidence shows that state and local tax activists do have a
powerful, if subtle, tool at their disposal. The "stick" spurring
efficient use of land is a higher tax rate upon land, up to even the
site's full annual value. The "carrot" rewarding efficient use of land
is a lower or zero tax rate upon improvements.
Owners paying higher land dues feel pressured
to develop their land in order to pay their dues, and development is
already blighting many suburbs and farmland. Won't the PTS force
premature or excessive development, losing open space and ecologically
sensitive areas? Environmentalists should understand that development
is actually needed to spare land. Using some land more intensely means
using other land not at all. The PTS stimulates construction in the
most intensely-used locations; compact urban form leaves more
surrounding countryside pristine. Since about one-fifth of urban areas
are vacant or underused land, and half is devoted to cars, there's
plenty of room in cities for growth. While suburban commercial centers
compete with downtown for redevelopment, each new building, whether for
business or residents, must find tenants.
Higher density is the expected result of the PTS, yet many people
oppose higher density. However, the noxious component is not a higher
density of population but of automobiles, creating congestion, noise,
noxious smells, and danger. The PTS, by clearing out the infestation of
vehicles, makes human habitats more livable and the added people
unnoticeable.
Without coercion or remote planning, the PTS improves our settlement
patterns. Regulations and zoning, some assume, might be vitiated or
obviated, become obsolete. Instead, the PTS makes it easier for
regulations and zoning to do their job. Since the land tax lowers land
price, buying land for parks and reserves is more easily afforded. The
loss in revenue from removing the newly public lands from the tax rolls
would be offset somewhat by the corresponding rise in value of sites
near the protected open space. Creating green spaces raises the density
of already developed land, and thus its value. Furthermore, land dues
reduce the profit from land development, making it a less attractive
investment, and land use decisions of less economic consequence. After
a while, people with deep pockets would turn to investments that,
post-shift, would be untaxed. Reserving land for recreational or
natural uses becomes less contentious; people could more easily
determine an optimum proportion of green space to developed space.
Redirecting land rent from owner to government might merely pass the
motive to exploit from owner to state, possibly the next implacable
force against conservation. However, while an individual must use their
own land most intensely to maximize profit, a government must optimize
land use to maximize its land tax base. That is, land value thruout the
jurisdiction is lower when there is border-to-border development;
overall values are higher when some space is kept open. From the
government's point of view, there's more rent to be collected when
highest and best use includes nonuse.
A big problem needs a big solution which in turn
needs a
matching shift of our prevailing paradigm. Geonomics -- advocating that
we share the social value of sites and natural resources and untax
earnings -- does just that. Read the whole article
Jeff Smith: How Profit
Shapes Urban Space
Like the rest of the universe, US
cities keep expanding. Some time before the
universe begins to contract, American metro
regions may, too. What counterpart to gravity might suck
suburbia back into the hole of our doughnut cities? One of the most
fundamental forces in the world - money. ...
Without spending a penny of subsidy,
cities can make
urban renewal more profitable than
suburban
development. How is about as
commonsensical as
Einsteinian physics, but like "e=mc2",
it works. The trick
is to forget subsidies and lower one
tax while raising
another. That is, levy a tax or charge
a fee to collect
land value while eliminating any tax
on buildings or
improvements.
The present property tax works
backwards, like an
intruder from the anti-universe. It
increases as owners
improve their property; it decreases
when owners let
buildings dilapidate. "Save money,
create slums," cities
tell owners.
Some owners do keep prime sites
covered with parking
lots or abandoned buildings while
waiting for land
values to rise. "Good numbers are hard
to come by,"
notes Bill Batt, former fiscal policy
researcher for the
New York legislature, "but easily a
quarter of a US city
is under-utilized." Thus
urban cores decay, an
entropy that seems
natural and inevitable yet
is policy-induced.
If the property tax is a
centrifugal force that
flings structures
outward, its opposite is
a land levy, a centripetal
force that pulls development inward.
To pay this
charge, owners try to put their
parcels to better use.
"Owners of the most valuable sites,
paying the most,
try hardest," explains Tom Gihring, a
Seattle-based
consultant.. "Since the most valuable
lots lie about the
center, it is the center which draws development." In-fill
happens.
... Read the whole article
Jeff Smith: Planning by
Markets
... Since we do
not collectively build homes and businesses -- homeowners and
business owners do that --we ought not tax them. We do generate the
value of land, higher where density is higher. Nobody by himself made
density; we all do that. Via our agent, a local government, we could
collect public rent for public betterment.
Planners have a litany of great
ideas for rebuilding cities(4)
-- set-backs, landscaping,
pedestrian bridges, bridges, etc -- but have no idea of how to pay
for them. One way is to let them pay for themselves. Improving a city
raises its land's value. A tax or fee can collect this ground rent
that can then be used to pay off the earlier investment in
ecologizing the city(5).
Indeed, the expected change in land value can be a perfect measure of
some proposed improvement's worthiness. If it can pay its way, throw
it up. If it can't, then back to the drawing board.
No longer inhibited by the
property tax
yet spurred by annual land dues (tax or fee), owners and developers
get busy. Some Australian
towns that tax land alone average 50 percent more built value per
acre than those that don't. Since a mix of apartments, stores, offices,
schools, theaters, etc. maximizes site value and the return to
builders, they could find themselves pulling on the same end of the
rope with planners.
Where planners, armed with the
sternest growth control measures,
have failed, geonomics can succeed. By making speculation too
expensive, it unplugs the "metro tub", letting the flow of
development return to its natural course, filling in the vacant lots
and abandoned buildings. Clever local governments,
no longer able to tax willy-nilly and thus more dependent upon site
rent, would squeeze streets, now overly wide for traffic, replacing
parking lanes with space for sidewalk cafes beneath rows of shady
trees, alongside lanes for bikes, and thereby drive up site values.
... How long would it take
to ecologize cities after shifting its
property tax? While Johannesburg (South African) levied a rate of
only 3 percent on site value, it enjoyed the fastest site-recycling
rate in the world, a little over 20 years. Within a couple decades,
we could have those cities we'd love.
As cities grow more livable and
lovable, their site values rise.
The resultant increase in land dues would push owners to continually
convert to highest and best use automatically. In this positive
feedback loop, cities would constantly renew.
While generals and anarchists
might not easily find common cause,
planners and markets can, when planners paddle with, not against, the
mighty current of rent. Correcting the market, so that taxes and
rents no longer interfere with the choices of owners and developers,
would attain highest and best use of sites automatically. Read the whole article
Michael Hudson and Kris Feder: Real Estate and the Capital
Gains Debate
Economic policy should
distinguish between activities which add to
productive capacity and those which merely add to overhead This
distinction
elevates the policy debate above the level of merely carping about
inequitable wealth
distribution, an attack by have-nots on the haves, to the fundamental
issues. What ways of getting
income deserve fiscal encouragement, and how may economic surpluses
best be tapped to
support government needs? Policies
that subsidize rentier incomes
while
penalizing productive effort have grave implications, not only for
distributive justice and
social harmony, but also for economic efficiency and growth.
Herbert J. G. Bab: Property
Tax -- Cause of Unemployment (circa 1964)
Property taxes shape the pattern
of our cities.
- If taxes on improvements are low or non-existing and taxes
on
land are high, the cities are bound to grow vertically and at a fast
rate.
- If taxes on improvements are high and taxes on land are
low, our
cities will spread over larger and larger areas. They will become
metropolitan areas and they will grow at a much slower rate.
Relatively low taxes on land and
high taxes on improvements will
discourage the owners of vacant lots or underdeveloped land, such as
that used for parking lots, gas stations, hamburger stands, etc., from
improving their land. It will encourage them to keep the land out of
use and to sell later at a profit. This will create an artificial
shortage of land, which in turn will lead to urban blight and
irregular, leapfrog city growth.
This urban sprawl makes our cities look ugly, but it has many
disadvantages besides:
- It gobbles up a tremendous amount of farm land;
- the farmers have to give up their land before it is really
needed;
- the building developer has to go far out to find available
land;
- the prospective home-owner has to travel farther;
- traffic on congested roads will increase and
- new roads and schools will have to be built.
It
is generally believed that zoning
laws are a very effective tool to control the growth of our cities.
Zoning laws determine the best possible use of urban land. Yet nobody
can be forced to improve his land and to build unless there is an
incentive. This can be achieved by taxing land at a rate that will make
it unprofitable to hold it without improving it.
The city planner needs land taxation just as he needs zoning
laws. With
both these tools the orderly growth of our cities will be assured, but
-- as experience has shown -- without land taxation rational and
efficient land usage becomes impossible. Read
the whole article
Bill Batt: The Merits of Site
Value Taxation
One must begin a
discussion by recognizing that governments,
constitutionally speaking, have two means by which to effectuate public
policy, conventionally known as tax powers and police powers.1 The
primary purpose of taxing power historically has been to raise the
necessary revenue to support government functions as defined by the
electorate through its chosen representatives. Many students of
government argue that this should be its only purpose. President
Reagan, for example, reflected this view of taxation when he stated in
1981 that "the taxing power of the government must be used to provide
for legitimate government purposes. It must not be used to regulate the
economy or bring about social change."2 This
view has within it the implicit view that there is a way to tax that is
totally neutral in its influence on economic behavior, something which
has not always been understood or agreed to. Taxes have always been
used to facilitate socioeconomic policies, and in recent years have
become a conscious tool of policy makers even more. One recent study
notes that in the state of Washington, for example, 222 of the 378
identifiable tax breaks for special purposes have been enacted since
1970; the state of Oregon, similarly, has witnessed 288.3 But
whether using taxing powers to facilitate other purposes is a wise and
efficient approach needs to be more carefully considered, and there has
been too little discussion of this issue in contemporary scholarship or
political life. Furthermore, only recently has it been possible to
understand the possibility of tax neutrality. ...
... Not all revenue collection on the part
of government is grounded in
the
constitutional authority of its tax powers. Taxes in the strictest
sense of the term are revenues involuntarily paid to general funds for
the general purposes of government. But there are many other revenues
paid to government that would never be construed as taxes: lottery
revenues, fines, interest payments, environmental (green) fees, payment
for information, and user fees being the most common examples. Fines,
green fees, and user fees are instruments of police power precisely
because their primary purpose is to correct behavior, and only
secondarily to raise revenue. User fees, along with environmental fees
particularly, are employed to recover the costs of use, wear or damage
to environmental or government-provided "services." (Only in recent
years has it been fashionable to regard use or degradation of the
natural environment as a "service," necessitating "correction," as was
originally explicated by Pigou earlier this century.
Fiscal measures such as those noted above can be employed under
police
powers to correct, or at least compensate for, otherwise egregious
social behavior, and public policy makers must concern themselves with
the question whether such measures are more or less appropriate or
effective. These provide an attractive alternative to what have come to
be known as "command and control" approaches. Just as are so many
fiscal measures, command-and-control approaches to regulating and
controlling social and economic behavior is also grounded in the police
powers of government. Administrative theory has grown in appreciation
for fiscal approaches and away from command-and-control approaches in
recent years.8 This
is because they are often far less expensive and more efficient to implement,
easier to understand, have a greater degree of compliance,
and has the added virtue, lastly, of raising revenue for the support of
governmental responsibilities. This interest in "tax shifting" has
inspired the slogan, "Tax
Bads, Not Goods."... Read the whole piece
Bill Batt: The Nexus of
Transportation, Economic Rent, and Land Use
... To secure the fullest
results of collecting land rent, structures
should be removed entirely from revenue base and imposed on the land
component alone. Phasing out the tax burden on improvements and placing
it on land value alone removes the penalty now placed on those who do
invest in and maintain their buildings. And, as mentioned earlier, it
prompts titleholders to abjure practices for speculative gain. If only
the land value component of the property tax is collected and tax on
buildings is eliminated, those who do use landsites to the full extent
that their value warrants are rewarded for doing so. ...
Correcting Distortions by
Pricing:
Increasing the Collection of Land Rent
Recovering the economic rent from urban parcels helps people to
appreciate the true costs of the transportation versus location
trade-off. It brings the carrying costs of site choices back to the
present time and makes them comparable with travel choices. The payment
of site rent becomes an operating cost. The other corrective policy
needed is to raise transportation costs to a level commensurate with
their full value as private goods. Transportation user fees, in the
form of motor fuel taxes, green taxes, congestion fees, and
administrative costs (for the administration of drivers' licenses and
registration fees) could easily provide the needed price corrections to
bring into balance marginal transportation costs and land rent
collection. Doing so would equilibrate choices between people living
and working in high rent urban centers and those in peripheral low rent
(but higher travel cost) locales.
Figure 2 shows how a tax on land value (or alternatively the tax
on
land rent) coupled with the proper design of transportation fees can
equilibrate the competitive advantage of markets in urban areas
relative to suburbs, thereby reducing, and perhaps even reversing, the
centrifugal forces of sprawl development. The land tax cannot alone
redress the problem, especially so long as such inordinate social
subsidies are granted to private motor vehicle transportation services.
Nor can transportation fees, raised to a level fully commensurate with
the social and private costs they incur, alone ensure that the price of
locations will be matched. But to the extent that both are assessed,
they reach far toward correcting this disequilibrium. One could even
argue that all site rent should be recaptured by society and that all
transportation costs that are identifiable as consumption of private
goods should be priced accordingly. Some advocates even suggest that
doing so will not only foster economic efficient behavior but also
provide sufficient revenue for a citizen's dividend consistent with
economic justice.... read the whole article
Bill Batt: Comment on Parts of
the NYS Legislative Tax Study Commission's 1985 study “Who Pays New
York Taxes?”
Henry George’s Solution: Taxing the Flow of Land Rent
If land values are really the present values of anticipated future ground
rents, one can certainly treat them as flows rather than stocks, just as
community services are continuous flows. The amount of rent flowing through
a site and through the economy is not negligible; what estimates have been
made, where indeed the economic data allow it to be made, suggest that it
is roughly a third of a nation’s GDP.29 The question is whether it
makes more sense to. Should we elect to continue property tax regimes as
we do, it would make better sense to tax buildings as stocks and lands as
rent flows. But this raises the question whether real property should be
exempt from all taxes, as some have argued.30 What rationale exists for taxing
lands, whether as stocks or flows; and why do we tax buildings? I will argue
below that taxing buildings and the failure to adequately tax land both have
deleterious consequences for the whole economy.
Little justification exists for taxing buildings, or improvements
of any sort, so this question is easily disposed of. The practice is explained
largely
as a matter of historical inertia. Only in the recent century or two have
buildings represented any significant capital value; prior to the rise of
major cities, the value of real property lay essentially in land. American
cities today typically record aggregate assessed land values – at least
when the valuations are well-done – at about 40% to 60% of total taxable
value, that is, of land and buildings taken together.31 Skyscrapers reflect
enormous capital investment, and this expenditure is warranted because of
the enormous value of locational sites. Each site gets its market price from
the fact that the total neighborhood context creates an attractive market
presence and ambience. By taxing buildings, however, we impose a penalty
on their optimum development as well as on the incentives for their maintenance.
Moreover, taxes on buildings take away from whatever burden would
otherwise be imposed on sites, with the result that incentives for their
highest and
best use is weakened. Lastly, the technical and administrative challenges
of properly assessing the value of improvements is daunting, particularly
since they must be depreciated for tax and accounting purposes, evaluated
for potential replacement, and so on. In fact most costs associated with
administration of property taxation and appeal litigation involve disputes
over the valuation of structures, not land values. ... read the whole commentary
Bill Batt: How Our Towns Got That
Way (1996 speech)
Failure to recapture
publicly-created land rents through the
tax mechanism provided the incentive to speculators to buy land, not
to use it in production but to hold it for the rise. In this way,
choice parcels remain undeveloped or underdeveloped relative to the
full extent that their values warrant and development occurs instead
in remote areas where opportunity for profit is more immediate. The
result was low density development what we know as sprawl.
To some people this may be
counter-intuitive. It may not be
obvious that increasing taxes on a parcel of land will foster its
improvement. Consider, however, the
possibility that there are two
parcels of land in roughly the same location and of equal size. You
own a vacant parcel and another next to it has a twenty-story
building. If only the land-value is taxed you will be paying the same
tax revenue as your neighbor. What
are you likely to do with your
parcel? If you are
rational, you will either build a twenty-story
building or else sell the land to someone who will. In this way
improvements tend to be clustered in high-land-value areas except
where it is prohibited, perhaps for a park. ... read
the whole article
Wyn Achenbaum: Eminent Domain
and Government Giveaways
It seems to me that there are better ways than eminent domain to provide
the incentives that will lead the private sector to develop choice land. ...
While at one time this area might have been an appropriate place for a neighborhood
of single family homes, it appeared to me that that time had passed a decade
or so ago. It seemed to me that the path of progress would -- if the incentives
were logical and the market responsive to signals -- have caused the private
sector to have redeveloped that site. Such re-development might have been
painful to the residents of the neighborhood, but would have put now-choice
land to a higher and better use than single-family homes.
But our system wasn't designed to send signals all that well -- Connecticut
law required properties to be reassessed once every decade (and I've heard
that once in early '70s and once in the late 80's was construed to satisfy
that requirement). Now assessments are required every 4 years (though my
town decided it didn't like the 2003 revaluation and is keeping the 1999
for a few more years).
But if the properties had been reassessed on a regular basis, with market-based
values assigned first to the land and the residual being assigned to the
existing buildings, the homeowners themselves would have been in a position
to make their own rational decisions on whether it was worth it to them to
continue to occupy extremely valuable land (and pay the taxes on it), or
more to their advantage to accept an offer from someone who was prepared
to put it to a higher and better use, and take that equity and buy elsewhere. ...
Our land, particularly the best-located land, is a common asset on which
we are all dependent. Allowing individuals or corporations to occupy it without
compensating the rest of us for its value is the underlying problem, and
solving that problem through good assessment and rational (that is, land
value) taxes is the way to solve it. When we do that, a lot of problems will
begin to fall away. Read
the whole article
The case for site value rating in terms of economic efficiency is founded
on the fact that a tax on resources that are not produced by human effort
is one of the few sources of government revenue that does not reduce incentives
for people to be productive. Two other revenue sources that have this virtue
are taxes on other government-granted privileges such as exclusive use of
radio frequencies and taxes on activities with harmful consequences, such
as polluting the air. An economy will be more efficient if revenue sources
that do not diminish productivity are employed to the greatest possible extent
before any use is made of taxes that impede productivity.
What makes a tax efficient is that the amount of tax that is
due cannot be reduced by reducing productive activities. When incomes are
taxed, people
can reduce the amount of taxes owed by working less. They do so, and the
productivity of the economy falls. When houses are taxed, people can reduce
the amount of taxes owed by building fewer house and smaller houses. They
do so, and the housing shortage worsens. But when the unimproved value of
land is taxed, there is no resulting diminution in the quantity of land.
Thus taxes can be levied on land without diminishing the productivity of
an economy. And shifting taxes from other, destructive bases to land will
improve the productivity of an economy. ... read the whole article
Land value taxation generalizes into the principle that people should pay
for all of their appropriations of natural opportunities, according to
the opportunity costs of those appropriations, and the resulting revenue
should
be shared equally. ...
Taxing land has an additional effect that increases the stock of capital.
A tax on land represents a redistribution from living adults to the young
and unborn, who will now be born with rights to land. Unless there is a perfectly
offsetting reduction in the desire to accumulate assets to transfer to the
next generation, this redistribution will induce the living, who now have
fewer assets, to accumulate at a more rapid rate than they would otherwise
do. That is, saving and capital accumulation will increase.
Taxing land also increases the efficiency with which land is used. This
occurs through three paths.
- First, a tax on land reduces the return to land speculation, and therefore
reduces the quantity of land speculation.
- Second, as taxes on land are capitalized into the selling price of land,
the result is the substitution of a recurring
cost (the annual tax) for a one-time cost (the purchase price). This makes
land
relatively more attractive
to bidders with high discount rates and relatively
less attractive to bidders with low discount rates. To the extent that
the former are more entrepreneurial
and the latter more passive investors, land will
tend to flow into the hands of persons who will choose to use it more intensively.
- The third path by which a tax on land increases the efficiency with
which land is used is that, for those who are using land
inefficiently, it substitutes an explicit cost (the tax) for an implicit
one (the income foregone by
inefficient use).
Psychologically, explicit costs tend to be more
effective in motivating efficient behavior than implicit ones. .. read
the whole article
|
To
share this page with a friend: right click, choose "send," and
add your comments.
|
|
Red
links have not been visited; .
Green
links are pages you've seen |
Essential Documents
pertinent to this theme:
|
|