Hunter-Gatherer Societies
Henry George: The Condition of
Labor — An
Open Letter to Pope Leo XIII in response to Rerum Novarum (1891)
As to the use of land, we hold: That —
While the right of ownership that justly attaches to things produced by
labor cannot attach to land, there may attach to land a right of possession.
As your Holiness says, “God has not granted the earth to mankind in
general in the sense that all without distinction can deal with it as they
please,” and regulations necessary for its best use may be fixed by
human laws. But such regulations must conform to the moral law — must
secure to all equal participation in the advantages of God’s general
bounty. The principle is the same as where a human father leaves property
equally to a number of children. Some of the things thus left may be incapable
of common use or of specific division. Such things may properly be assigned
to some of the children, but only under condition that the equality of benefit
among them all be preserved.
In the rudest social state, while industry consists in hunting, fishing,
and gathering the spontaneous fruits of the earth, private possession of
land is not necessary. But as men begin to cultivate the ground and expend
their labor in permanent works, private possession of the land on which labor
is thus expended is needed to secure the right of property in the products
of labor. For who would sow if not assured of the exclusive possession needed
to enable him to reap? who would attach costly works to the soil without
such exclusive possession of the soil as would enable him to secure the benefit?
This right of private possession in things created by God is however very
different from the right of private ownership in things produced by labor.
The one is limited, the other unlimited, save in cases when the dictate of
self-preservation terminates all other rights. The purpose of the one, the
exclusive possession of land, is merely to secure the other, the exclusive
ownership of the products of labor; and it can never rightfully be carried
so far as to impair or deny this. While any one may hold exclusive possession
of land so far as it does not interfere with the equal rights of others,
he can rightfully hold it no further.
Thus Cain and Abel, were there only two men on earth, might by
agreement divide the earth between them. Under this compact each
might
claim exclusive right to his share as against the other. But
neither could
rightfully
continue such claim against the next man born. For since
no one comes into the world
without God’s permission, his presence attests his
equal right to the use of God’s bounty. For them
to refuse him any use of the earth which they had divided
between them would
therefore be for
them to commit
murder.
And for them to refuse him any use of the earth, unless
by laboring for them or by giving them part of the products
of
his labor
he bought it
of them,
would be for them to commit theft. ...
God’s laws do not change. Though their applications may alter with
altering conditions, the same principles of right and wrong that hold when
men are few and industry is rude also hold amid teeming populations and complex
industries. In our cities of millions and our states of scores of millions,
in a civilization where the division of labor has gone so far that large
numbers are hardly conscious that they are land-users, it still remains true
that we are all land animals and can live only on land, and that land is
God’s bounty to all, of which no one can be deprived without being
murdered, and for which no one can be compelled to pay another without being
robbed. But even in a state of society where the elaboration of industry
and the increase of permanent improvements have made the need for private
possession of land wide-spread, there is no difficulty in conforming individual
possession with the equal right to land. For as soon as any piece of land
will yield to the possessor a larger return than is had by similar labor
on other land a value attaches to it which is shown when it is sold or rented.
Thus, the value of the land itself, irrespective of the value of any improvements
in or on it, always indicates the precise value of the benefit to which all
are entitled in its use, as distinguished from the value which, as producer
or successor of a producer, belongs to the possessor in individual right.
To combine the advantages of private possession with the justice of common
ownership it is only necessary therefore to take for common uses what value
attaches to land irrespective of any exertion of labor on it. The principle
is the same as in the case referred to, where a human father leaves equally
to his children things not susceptible of specific division or common use.
In that case such things would be sold or rented and the value equally applied.
It is on this common-sense principle that we, who term ourselves single-tax
men, would have the community act.
We do not propose to assert equal rights to land by keeping land common,
letting any one use any part of it at any time. We do not propose the task,
impossible in the present state of society, of dividing land in equal shares;
still less the yet more impossible task of keeping it so divided.
We propose — leaving land in the private possession of individuals,
with full liberty on their part to give, sell or bequeath it — simply
to levy on it for public uses a tax that shall equal the annual value of
the land itself, irrespective of the use made of it or the improvements on
it. And since this would provide amply for the need of public revenues, we
would accompany this tax on land values with the repeal of all taxes now
levied on the products and processes of industry — which taxes, since
they take from the earnings of labor, we hold to be infringements of the
right of property.
This we propose, not as a cunning device of human ingenuity, but as a conforming
of human regulations to the will of God.
God cannot contradict himself nor impose on his creatures laws that clash.
If it be God’s command to men that they should not steal — that
is to say, that they should respect the right of property which each one
has in the fruits of his labor;
And if he be also the Father of all men, who in his common bounty has intended
all to have equal opportunities for sharing;
Then, in any possible stage of civilization, however elaborate, there must
be some way in which the exclusive right to the products of industry may
be reconciled with the equal right to land.
If the Almighty be consistent with himself, it cannot be, as say those socialists
referred to by you, that in order to secure the equal participation of men
in the opportunities of life and labor we must ignore the right of private
property. Nor yet can it be, as you yourself in the Encyclical seem to argue,
that to secure the right of private property we must ignore the equality
of right in the opportunities of life and labor. To say the one thing or
the other is equally to deny the harmony of God’s laws.
But, the private possession of land, subject to the payment to the community
of the value of any special advantage thus given to the individual, satisfies
both laws, securing to all equal participation in the bounty of the Creator
and to each the full ownership of the products of his labor. ...
Nor do we hesitate to say that this way of securing the equal right to the
bounty of the Creator and the exclusive right to the products of labor is
the way intended by God for raising public revenues. For we are not atheists,
who deny God; nor semi-atheists, who deny that he has any concern in politics
and legislation.
It is true as you say — a salutary truth too often forgotten — that “man
is older than the state, and he holds the right of providing for the life
of his body prior to the formation of any state.” Yet, as you too perceive,
it is also true that the state is in the divinely appointed order. For He
who foresaw all things and provided for all things, foresaw and provided
that with the increase of population and the development of industry the
organization of human society into states or governments would become both
expedient and necessary.
No sooner does the state arise than, as we all know, it needs revenues.
This need for revenues is small at first, while population is sparse, industry
rude and the functions of the state few and simple. But with growth of population
and advance of civilization the functions of the state increase and larger
and larger revenues are needed.
Now, He that made the world and placed man in it, He that pre-ordained civilization
as the means whereby man might rise to higher powers and become more and
more conscious of the works of his Creator, must have foreseen this increasing
need for state revenues and have made provision for it. That is to say: The
increasing need for public revenues with social advance, being a natural,
God-ordained need, there must be a right way of raising them — some
way that we can truly say is the way intended by God. It is clear that this
right way of raising public revenues must accord with the moral law.
Hence:
- It must not take from individuals what rightfully belongs to individuals.
- It must not give some an advantage over others, as by increasing the prices
of what some have to sell and others must buy.
- It must not lead men into temptation, by requiring trivial oaths, by making
it profitable to lie, to swear falsely, to bribe or to take bribes.
- It must not confuse the distinctions of right and wrong, and weaken the
sanctions of religion and the state by creating crimes that are not sins,
and punishing men for doing what in itself they have an undoubted right
to do.
- It must not repress industry. It must not check commerce. It must not punish
thrift. It must offer no impediment to the largest production and the
fairest division of wealth.
Let me ask your Holiness to consider the taxes on the processes and products
of industry by which through the civilized world public revenues are collected — the
octroi duties that surround Italian cities with barriers; the monstrous customs
duties that hamper intercourse between so-called Christian states; the taxes
on occupations, on earnings, on investments, on the building of houses, on
the cultivation of fields, on industry and thrift in all forms. Can these
be the ways God has intended that governments should raise the means they
need? Have any of them the characteristics indispensable in any plan we can
deem a right one?
All these taxes violate the moral law. They take by force what belongs to
the individual alone; they give to the unscrupulous an advantage over the
scrupulous; they have the effect, nay are largely intended, to increase the
price of what some have to sell and others must buy; they corrupt government;
they make oaths a mockery; they shackle commerce; they fine industry and
thrift; they lessen the wealth that men might enjoy, and enrich some by impoverishing
others.
Yet what most strikingly shows how opposed to Christianity is this system
of raising public revenues is its influence on thought.
Christianity teaches us that all men are brethren; that their true interests
are harmonious, not antagonistic. It gives us, as the golden rule of life,
that we should do to others as we would have others do to us. But out of
the system of taxing the products and processes of labor, and out of its
effects in increasing the price of what some have to sell and others must
buy, has grown the theory of “protection,” which denies this
gospel, which holds Christ ignorant of political economy and proclaims laws
of national well-being utterly at variance with his teaching. This theory
sanctifies national hatreds; it inculcates a universal war of hostile tariffs;
it teaches peoples that their prosperity lies in imposing on the productions
of other peoples restrictions they do not wish imposed on their own; and
instead of the Christian doctrine of man’s brotherhood it makes injury
of foreigners a civic virtue.
“By their fruits ye shall know them.” Can anything more clearly
show that to tax the products and processes of industry is not the way God
intended public revenues to be raised?
But to consider what we propose — the raising of public revenues by
a single tax on the value of land irrespective of improvements — is
to see that in all respects this does conform to the moral law.
Let me ask your Holiness to keep in mind that the value we propose to tax,
the value of land irrespective of improvements, does not come from any exertion
of labor or investment of capital on or in it — the values produced
in this way being values of improvement which we would exempt. The value
of land irrespective of improvement is the value that attaches to land by
reason of increasing population and social progress. This is a value that
always goes to the owner as owner, and never does and never can go to the
user; for if the user be a different person from the owner he must always
pay the owner for it in rent or in purchase-money; while if the user be also
the owner, it is as owner, not as user, that he receives it, and by selling
or renting the land he can, as owner, continue to receive it after he ceases
to be a user.
Thus, taxes on land irrespective of improvement cannot lessen the rewards
of industry, nor add to prices,* nor in any way take from the individual
what belongs to the individual. They can take only the value that attaches
to land by the growth of the community, and which therefore belongs to the
community as a whole.
* As to this point it may be well to add that all economists
are agreed that taxes on land values irrespective of improvement or use — or
what in the terminology of political economy is styled rent, a term distinguished
from the ordinary use of the word rent by being applied solely to payments
for the use of land itself — must be paid by the owner and cannot
be shifted by him on the user. To explain in another way the reason given
in the text: Price is not determined by the will of the seller or the
will of the buyer, but by the equation of demand and supply, and therefore
as to things constantly demanded and constantly produced rests at a point
determined by the cost of production — whatever tends to increase
the cost of bringing fresh quantities of such articles to the consumer
increasing price by checking supply, and whatever tends to reduce such
cost decreasing price by increasing supply. Thus taxes on wheat or tobacco
or cloth add to the price that the consumer must pay, and thus the cheapening
in the cost of producing steel which improved processes have made in
recent years has greatly reduced the price of steel. But land has no
cost of production, since it is created by God, not produced by man.
Its price therefore is fixed —
1 (monopoly rent), where land is held in close monopoly,
by what the owners can extract from the users under penalty of deprivation
and consequently of starvation, and amounts to all that common labor
can earn on it beyond what is necessary to life;
2 (economic rent proper), where there is no special monopoly, by what the
particular land will yield to common labor over and above what may be had
by like expenditure and exertion on land having no special advantage and
for which no rent is paid; and,
3 (speculative rent, which is a species of monopoly rent, telling particularly
in selling price), by the expectation of future increase of value from
social growth and improvement, which expectation causing landowners to
withhold land at present prices has the same effect as combination.
Taxes on land values or economic rent can therefore never
be shifted by the landowner to the land-user, since they in no wise increase
the demand for land or enable landowners to check supply by withholding
land from use. Where rent depends on mere monopolization, a case I mention
because rent may in this way be demanded for the use of land even before
economic or natural rent arises, the taking by taxation of what the landowners
were able to extort from labor could not enable them to extort any more,
since laborers, if not left enough to live on, will die. So, in the case
of economic rent proper, to take from the landowners the premiums they
receive, would in no way increase the superiority of their land and the
demand for it. While, so far as price is affected by speculative rent,
to compel the landowners to pay taxes on the value of land whether they
were getting any income from it or not, would make it more difficult
for them to withhold land from use; and to tax the full value would not
merely destroy the power but the desire to do so.
To take land values for the state, abolishing all taxes on the products
of labor, would therefore leave to the laborer the full produce of labor;
to the individual all that rightfully belongs to the individual. It would
impose no burden on industry, no check on commerce, no punishment on thrift;
it would secure the largest production and the fairest distribution of wealth,
by leaving men free to produce and to exchange as they please, without any
artificial enhancement of prices; and by taking for public purposes a value
that cannot be carried off, that cannot be hidden, that of all values is
most easily ascertained and most certainly and cheaply collected, it would
enormously lessen the number of officials, dispense with oaths, do away with
temptations to bribery and evasion, and abolish man-made crimes in themselves
innocent.
But, further: That God has intended the state to obtain the revenues it
needs by the taxation of land values is shown by the same order and degree
of evidence that shows that God has intended the milk of the mother for the
nourishment of the babe.
See how close is the analogy. In that primitive condition ere the
need for the state arises there are no land values. The products of labor
have value,
but in the sparsity of population no value as yet attaches to land itself. But as increasing density of population and increasing elaboration of industry
necessitate the organization of the state, with its need for revenues, value
begins to attach to land. As population still increases and industry grows
more elaborate, so the needs for public revenues increase. And at the same
time and from the same causes land values increase. The connection is invariable.
The value of things produced by labor tends to decline with social development,
since the larger scale of production and the improvement of processes tend
steadily to reduce their cost. But the value of land on which population
centers goes up and up. Take Rome or Paris or London or New York or Melbourne.
Consider the enormous value of land in such cities as compared with the value
of land in sparsely settled parts of the same countries. To what is this
due? Is it not due to the density and activity of the populations of those
cities — to the very causes that require great public expenditure for
streets, drains, public buildings, and all the many things needed for the
health, convenience and safety of such great cities? See how with the growth
of such cities the one thing that steadily increases in value is land; how
the opening of roads, the building of railways, the making of any public
improvement, adds to the value of land. Is it not clear that here is a natural
law — that is to say a tendency willed by the Creator? Can it mean
anything else than that He who ordained the state with its needs has in the
values which attach to land provided the means to meet those needs?
That it does mean this and nothing else is confirmed if we look deeper still,
and inquire not merely as to the intent, but as to the purpose of the intent.
If we do so we may see in this natural law by which land values increase
with the growth of society not only such a perfectly adapted provision for
the needs of society as gratifies our intellectual perceptions by showing
us the wisdom of the Creator, but a purpose with regard to the individual
that gratifies our moral perceptions by opening to us a glimpse of his beneficence.
Consider: Here is a natural law by which as society advances the one
thing that increases in value is land — a natural law by virtue
of which all growth of population, all advance of the arts, all general
improvements
of whatever kind, add to a fund that both the commands of justice and
the dictates of expediency prompt us to take for the common uses of society.
Now, since increase in the fund available for the common uses of society
is increase in the gain that goes equally to each member of society,
is it
not clear that the law by which land values increase with social advance
while the value of the products of labor does not increase, tends with
the advance of civilization to make the share that goes equally to each
member
of society more and more important as compared with what goes to him
from his individual earnings, and thus to make the advance of civilization
lessen
relatively the differences that in a ruder social state must exist between
the strong and the weak, the fortunate and the unfortunate? Does it not
show the purpose of the Creator to be that the advance of man in civilization
should be an advance not merely to larger powers but to a greater and
greater
equality, instead of what we, by our ignoring of his intent, are making
it, an advance toward a more and more monstrous inequality? ... read the whole letter
Gems from George, a themed collection
of excerpts from the writings of Henry
George (with links to sources)
THE aggregate produce of the labor of a savage tribe is small, but each
member is capable of an independent life. He can build his own habitation,
hew out or stitch together his own canoe, make his own clothing, manufacture
his own weapons, snares, tools and ornaments. He has all the knowledge of
nature possessed by his tribe — knows what vegetable productions are
fit for food, and where they maybe found; knows the habits and resorts of
beasts, birds, fishes and insects; can pilot himself by the sun or the stars,
by the turning of blossoms or the mosses on the trees; is, in short, capable
of supplying all his wants. He may be cut off from his fellows and still
live; and thus possesses an independent power which makes him a free contracting
party in his relations to the community of which he is a member.
Compare with this savage the laborer in the lowest ranks of civilized society,
whose life is spent in producing but one thing, or oftener but the infinitesimal
part of one thing, out of the multiplicity of things that constitute the
wealth of society and go to supply even the most primitive wants; who not
only cannot make even the tools required for his work, but often works with
tools that he does not own, and can never hope to own. Compelled to even
closer and more continuous labor than the savage, and gaining by it no more
than the savage gets — the mere necessaries of life — he loses
the independence of the savage. He is not only unable to apply his own powers
to the direct satisfaction of his own wants, but, without the concurrence
of many others, he is unable to apply them indirectly to the satisfaction
of his wants. He is a mere link in an enormous chain of producers and consumers,
helpless to separate himself, and helpless to move, except as they move.
The worse his position in society, the more dependent is he on society; the
more utterly unable does he become to do anything for himself. The very power
of exerting his labor for the satisfaction of his wants passes from his own
control, and may be taken away or restored by the actions of others, or by
general causes over which he has no more influence than he has over the motions
of the solar system. The primeval curse comes to be looked upon as a boon,
and men think, and talk, and clamor, and legislate as though monotonous manual
labor in itself were a good and not an evil, an end and not a means. Under
such circumstances, the man loses the essential quality of manhood — the
godlike power of modifying and controlling conditions. He becomes a slave,
a machine, a commodity — a thing, in some respects, lower than the
animal.
I am no sentimental admirer of the savage state. I do not get my ideas of
the untutored children of nature from Rousseau, or Chateaubriand, or Cooper.
I am conscious of its material and mental poverty, and its low and narrow
range. I believe that civilization is not only the natural destiny of man,
but the enfranchisement, elevation, and refinement of all his powers, and
think that it is only in such moods as may lead him to envy the cud-chewing
cattle, that a man who is free to the advantages of civilization could look
with regret upon the savage state. But, nevertheless, I think no one who
will open his eyes to the facts, can resist the conclusion that there are
in the heart of our civilization large classes with whom the veriest savage
could not afford to exchange. It is my deliberate opinion that if, standing
on the threshold of being, one were given the choice of entering life as
a Terra del Fuegan, a black fellow of Australia, an Esquimaux in the Arctic
Circle, or among the lowest classes in such a highly civilized country as
Great Britain, he would make infinitely the better choice in selecting the
lot of the savage. For those classes who in the midst of wealth are condemned
to want, suffer all the privations of the savage, without his sense of personal
freedom; they are condemned to more than his narrowness and littleness, without
opportunity for the growth of his rude virtues; if their horizon is wider,
it is but to reveal blessings that they cannot enjoy. — Progress & Poverty — Book
V, Chapter 2: The Problem Solved: The Persistence of Poverty Amid Advancing
Wealth
LET us try to trace the genesis of civilization. Gifted alone with the
power of relating cause and effect, man is among all animals the only producer
in the true sense of the term. . . . But the same quality of reason which
makes him the producer, also, wherever exchange becomes possible, makes him
the exchanger. And it is along this line of exchanging that the body economic
is evolved and develops, and that all the advances of civilization are primarily
made. . . . With the beginning of exchange or trade among men this body economic
begins to form, and in its beginning civilization begins. . . . To find an
utterly uncivilized people, we must find a people among whom there is no
exchange or trade. Such a people does not exist, and, as far as our knowledge
goes, never did. To find a fully civilized people, we must find a people
among whom exchange or trade is absolutely free, and has reached the fullest
development to which human desires can carry it. There is, as yet, unfortunately,
no such people. — The Science of Political Economy — unabridged:
Book I, Chapter 5, The Meaning of Political Economy: The Origin and Genesis
of Civilization • abridged: Chapter 4, The Origin and Genesis of Civilization
WHEN we, come to analyze production, we find it to fall into three modes,
viz::
ADAPTING, or changing natural products either in form or in place so as to
fit them for the satisfaction of human desire.
GROWING, or utilizing the vital forces of nature, as by raising vegetables
or animals.
EXCHANGING, or utilizing, so as to add to the general sum of wealth, the
higher powers of those natural forces which vary with locality, or of those
human forces which vary with situation, occupation, or character. — Progress & Poverty — Book
III, Chapter 3, The Laws of Distribution: of Interest and the Cause of Interest
THESE modes seem to appear and to assume importance, in the development
of human society, much in the order here given. They originate from the increase
of the desires of men with the increase of the means of satisfying them,
under pressure of the fundamental law of political economy, that men seek
to satisfy their desires with the least exertion. In the primitive stage
of human life the readiest way of satisfying desires is by adapting to human
use what is found in existence. In a later and more settled stage it is discovered
that certain desires can be more easily and more fully satisfied by utilizing
the principle of growth and reproduction, as by cultivating vegetables and
breeding animals. And in a still later period of development, it becomes
obvious that certain desires can be better and more easily satisfied by exchange,
which brings out the principle of co-operation more fully and powerfully
than could obtain among unexchanging economic units. — The Science
of Political Economy unabridged: Book III, Chapter 2, The Production of Wealth:
The Three Modes of Production • abridged: Part III, Chapter 2, The
Production of Wealth: The Three Modes of Production ... go
to "Gems from George"
|
To
share this page with a friend: right click, choose "send," and
add your comments.
|
|
Red
links have not been visited; .
Green
links are pages you've seen |
Essential Documents
pertinent to this theme:
essential_documents |
|