Commons Sector
Peter Barnes: Capitalism
3.0: Preface (pages ix.-xvi)
Part 2 of the book focuses on capitalism as it could be, a version
I call Capitalism 3.0. The key difference between versions
2.0 and 3.0
is the
inclusion in the latter of a set of institutions I
call the commons sector. Instead
of having only one engine — that is, the corporate-dominated private
sector — our improved economic system would
run on two: one geared to maximizing private profit,
the
other to
preserving
and
enhancing common
wealth. ... read
the whole chapter
Peter Barnes: Capitalism
3.0 — Chapter 1: Time to Upgrade (pages 3-14)
Assets in the commons are meant to be preserved regardless of their return
to capital. Just as we receive them as shared gifts, so we have a duty to
pass them on in at least the same condition as we received them. If we can
add to their value, so much the better, but at a minimum we must not degrade
them, and we certainly have no right to destroy them.
Besides the commons, I use a few similar-sounding terms that should be clarified
here as well.
- By common wealth I mean the monetary and nonmonetary value of all
the assets in the commons. Like stockholders’ equity in a corporation,
it may increase or decrease from year to year depending on how well
the commons is managed.
- By common property I mean a class of human-made rights that lies
somewhere between private property and state property. Like private
property, common
property arises when the state recognizes it. Unlike private property,
it’s
inclusive rather than exclusive — it strives to share ownership
as widely, rather than as narrowly, as possible.
- By the commons sector I mean an organized
sector of our economy. It embraces some of the gifts we inherit together,
but not all.
In effect, it’s a
subset of the given commons that we consciously organize according
to commons principles. It’s small at the moment, but the point
of this book is that we should enlarge it. ... read
the whole chapter
Peter Barnes: Capitalism
3.0 — Chapter 5: Reinventing the Commons (pages 65-78)
Thus far I’ve argued that Capitalism 2.0 — or surplus capitalism — has
three tragic flaws: it devours nature, widens inequality, and fails to make
us happier in the end. It behaves this way because it’s programmed
to do so. It must make thneeds, reward property owners disproportionately,
and distract us from truer paths to happiness because its algorithms
direct it to do so. Neither enlightened managers nor the occasional zealous
regulator
can make it behave much differently.
In this part of the book I advance a solution. The essence of it
is to fix capitalism’s operating system by adding a commons sector to balance
the corporate sector. The new sector would supply virtuous feedback loops
and proxies for unrepresented stakeholders: future generations, pollutees,
and nonhuman species. And would offset the corporate sector’s negative
externalities with positive externalities of comparable magnitude. If the
corporate sector devours nature, the commons sector would protect it. If
the corporate sector widens inequality, the commons sector would reduce it.
If the corporate sector turns us into self-obsessed consumers, the commons
sector would reconnect us to nature, community, and culture. All this would
happen automatically once the commons sector is set up. The result would
be a balanced economy that gives us the best of both sectors and the worst
of neither.
To be sure, building an economic sector from scratch is a formidable task.
Fortunately, the commons sector needn’t be built from scratch; it has
an enormous potential asset base just waiting to be claimed. That asset base
is the commons itself, the gifts of nature and society we inherit and create
together. As we’ll see, these gifts are worth more than all private
assets combined. It’s the job of the commons sector to organize and
protect these gifts, and by so doing, to save capitalism from itself. ...
Organizing Principles of the Commons Sector
Property rights, especially the common kind, require competent institutions
to manage them. What we need today, then, along with more common property,
is a set of institutions, distinct from corporations and government, whose
unique and explicit mission is to manage common property.
I say set of institutions because there will and should be variety. The
commons sector should not be a monoculture like the corporate sector. Each
institution should be appropriate to its particular asset and locale.
Some of the variety will depend on whether the underlying asset is limited
or inexhaustible. Typically, gifts of nature have limited capacities; the
air can safely absorb only so much carbon dioxide, the oceans only so many
drift nets. Institutions that manage natural assets must therefore be capable
of limiting use. By contrast, ideas and cultural creations have endless potential
for elaboration and reuse. In these commons, managing institutions should
maximize public access and minimize private tollbooths.
Despite their variations, commons sector institutions would share a set
of organizing principles. Here are the main ones.
- LEAVE ENOUGH AND AS GOOD IN COMMON
As Locke argued, it’s okay to privatize parts of the commons as long
as “enough and as good” is left for everyone forever. Enough
in the case of an ecosystem means enough to keep it alive and healthy. That
much, or more, should be part of the commons, even if parts of the ecosystem
are private. In the case of culture and science, enough means enough to assure
a vibrant public domain. Exclusive licenses, such as patents and copyrights,
should be kept to a minimum.
- PUT FUTURE GENERATIONS FIRST
Corporations put the interests of stockholders first, while government puts
the interests of campaign donors and living voters first. No one at the moment
puts future generations first. That’s Job Number One for the commons
sector.
In practice, this means trustees of common property should be legally accountable
to future generations. (We’ll see how this might work in chapter 6.)
They should also be bound by the precautionary principle: when in doubt,
err on the side of safety. And when faced with a conflict between short-term
gain and long-term preservation, they should be required to choose the latter.
Whereas private property is inherently exclusive, common property strives
to be inclusive. It always wants more co-owners or participants, consistent
with preservation of the asset.
This organizing principle applies most clearly to commons like culture and
the Internet, where physical limits are absent and increasing use unleashes
synergies galore. It also applies to social compacts like Social Security
and Medicare, which require universal participation. In these compacts, financial
mechanisms express our solidarity with other members of our national community.
They’re efficient and fair because they include everybody. Were they
to operate under profit-maximizing principles, they’d inevitably exclude
the poor (who couldn’t afford to participate) and anyone deemed by
private insurers to be too risky.
Modern democratic government is grounded on the principle of one person,
one vote. In the same way, the modern commons sector would be grounded on
the principle of one person, one share. In the case of scarce natural assets,
it will be necessary to distinguish between usage rights and income rights.
It’s impossible for everyone to use a limited commons equally, but
everyone should receive equal shares of the income derived from selling limited
usage rights.
- INCLUDE SOME LIQUIDITY
Currently, private property owners enjoy a near-monopoly on the privilege
of receiving property income. But as the Alaska Permanent
Fund shows, it’s
possible for common property co-owners to receive income too.
Income sharing would end private property’s monopoly not only on liquidity,
but also on attention. People would notice common property if they got income
from it. They’d care about it, think about it, and talk about it. Concern
for invisible commons would soar.
Common property liquidity has to be designed carefully, though. Since
common property rights are birthrights, they shouldn’t be tradeable
the way corporate shares are. This means commons owners wouldn’t
reap capital gains. Instead, they’d retain their shared income
stakes throughout their lives, and through such stakes, share in rent,
royalties, interest,
and dividends. ... read
the whole chapter
|
To
share this page with a friend: right click, choose "send," and
add your comments.
|
|
Red
links have not been visited; .
Green
links are pages you've seen |
Essential Documents
pertinent to this theme:
essential_documents |
|