What Locke said in the Second Treatise,
Chapter V (On Property) [sec. 25] was:
"God, as king David says, Psal. cxv. 16. has given the earth to the children
of men; given it to mankind in common."
Sec. 26. God, who hath given the world to
men in common, hath also given them reason to make use of it to the best
advantage of life, and convenience. The earth, and all that is therein,
is given to men for the support and comfort of their being. And tho' all
the fruits it naturally produces, and beasts it feeds, belong to mankind
in common, as they are produced by the spontaneous hand of nature; and
no body has originally a private dominion, exclusive of the rest of mankind,
in any of them, as they are thus in their natural state:...
Sec. 27. Though the earth, and all inferior
creatures, be common to all men, yet every man has a property in his own
person: ...
For his labor being the unquestionable property of the laborer,
no man but he can have a right to what that is once joined to,
at least where there is enough, and as good, left in common for
others. — John Locke (1690)
Incidentally, a statement from John Stuart Mill is often erroneously
attributed to John Locke:
When the sacredness of property is talked of, it should be remembered
that any such sacredness does not belong in the same degree
to landed property.
D. C. MacDonald: Preface (1891?) to Ogilvie's Essay (circa 1782)
But why not utterly destroy this
monster? What better service for our
soldiers, blue-jackets, and policemen, than to employ themselves in
destroying this common enemy of mankind? Parliament could do it, a
royal warrant could do it, the sufferers have a right to do it, nay
“every man hath a right” to destroy such monsters. “In transgressing
the law of Nature,” says John Locke, “the offender declares himself to
live by another rule than that of reason and common equity, which is
that measure God has set to the actions of men for their mutual
security, and so he becomes dangerous to mankind; the tie which is to
secure them from injury and violence being slighted and broken by him,
which being a trespass against the whole species, and the peace and
safety of it, provided for by the law of Nature, every man upon this
score, by the right he hath to preserve mankind in general, may
restrain, or where it is necessary, destroy things noxious to them, and
so may bring such evil on any one who hath transgressed that law, as
may make him repent the doing of it, and thereby deter him, and, by his
example, others from doing the like mischief. And in this case, and
upon this ground, every man hath a right to punish the offender, and be
the executioner of the law of Nature.”*
*The renowned George Buchanan, the great-grand-father of
British Liberty, puts it even stronger than this.
... Read the entire preface
Dan Sullivan: Are you a Real
Libertarian, or a ROYAL Libertarian?
John Locke is often
misrepresented by royal libertarians, who
quote him very selectively. For example, Locke did say that:
Whatsoever then he
removes out of the state that nature
hath provided, and left it in, he hath mixed his labour with, and
joined to it something that is his own, and thereby makes it his
property.
But Locke condemned anyone who
took more than he needed as a
"spoiler of the commons":
...if the fruits rotted, or
the venison putrified,
before he could spend it, he offended against the common law of nature,
and was liable to be punished; he invaded his neighbour's share, for he
had no right, farther than his use called for any of them, and they
might serve to afford him conveniences of life.
The same measures governed
the possession of land too:
whatsoever he tilled and reaped, laid up and made use of, before it
spoiled, that was his peculiar right; whatsoever he enclosed, and could
feed, and make use of, the cattle and product was also his. But if
either the grass of his enclosure rotted on the ground, or the fruit of
his planting perished without gathering, and laying up, this part of
the earth, notwithstanding his enclosure, was still to be looked on as
waste, and might be the possession of any other.
Locke also restricted
appropriation of land by the proviso,
ignored by royal libertarians, that there must be still enough, and
as good left; and more than the yet unprovided could use. So that, in
effect, there was never the less left for others because of his
enclosure for himself: for he that leaves as much as another can make
use of, does as good as take nothing at all.
Now if the situation is that there
is enough free land, and as
good, left after you take and cultivate your land, than your land has
no market value, for who would pay you for land that is not better
than land that can be had for free? So, besides the fact that Locke's
justification of privatizing land is far more limited than royal
libertarians portray it to be, it is irrelevant to the question of
land value tax, as it applies only to land that has no value.
Furthermore, Locke based
his
scenario on pre-monetary societies,
where a landholder would find that "it was useless, as well as
dishonest, to carve himself too much, or take more than he needed."
With the introduction of money, Locke noted, all land quickly became
appropriated. Why? Because with money, those who can take more land
than they have personal use for suddenly have reason to do so, as
between them they will have taken all the land, and others will
have to pay rent to them. So, with the introduction of money, the
Lockean rationale for landed property falls apart, even according to
Locke.
And while Locke did not propose a
remedy specifically for to this
problem, he repeatedly stated that all taxes should be on real
estate.
... Read
the whole piece
Bill Batt: How Our Towns Got That
Way (1996 speech)
Rutgers Professor of Urban
Planning Donald Krueckeberg more
recently explained how real property became for the first time a
"commodity," much as the market gives personal property exchange
value. Native Americans tied the concept of property not to ownership
but to use. "One used it, one moved on, and use was shared with
others." But the colonists took their notion of real property from
evolving British legal tradition, defined largely in terms of what
its owners could subdue and control against challengers. John Locke's
conception of property was, in one sense, more akin to the Indian
notion in as much as one owned it only to the extent that one "mixed
one's labor" with it. ... read the whole article
These components of the
classical liberal conception of justice
are held by two groups that hold conflicting views on a companion
issue of great importance: how are claims of exclusive access to
natural opportunities to be established?
John Locke qualified his statement
that we own what we produce
with his famous "proviso" that there be "as much and as good left in
common for others." A few pages later, writing in the last decade of
the seventeenth century, he said that private appropriations of land
are actually not restricted, because anyone who is dissatisfied with
the land available to him in Europe can always go to America, where
there is plenty of unclaimed land.[12]
Locke does not address
the issue of rights to land when land is scarce.
One tradition in classical
liberalism concerning claims to land is
that of the "homesteading libertarians,"
as exemplified by Murray
Rothbard, who say that there is really no need to be concerned with
Locke's proviso. Natural opportunities belong to whoever first
appropriates them, regardless of whether opportunities of equal value
are available to others.[13]
The other tradition is that of the
"geoists,"
as inspired if not
exemplified by Henry George, who say that, whenever natural
opportunities are scarce, each person has an obligation to ensure
that the per capita value of the natural opportunities that he leaves
for others is as great as the value of the natural opportunities that
he claims for himself.[14] Any
excess in one's claim
generates an obligation to compensate those who thereby have less.
George actually proposed the nearly equivalent idea, that all or
nearly all of the rental value of land should be collected in taxes,
and all other taxes should be abolished. The geoist position as I
have expressed it emphasizes the idea that, at least when value
generated by public services is not an issue, rights to land are
fundamentally rights of individuals, not rights of governments.
There are two fundamental problems
with the position of
homesteading libertarians on claims to land. The first problem is the
incongruity with historical reality. Humans have emerged from an
environment of violence. Those who now have titles to land can trace
those titles back only so far, before they come to events where fiat
backed by violence determined title. And the persons who were
displaced at that time themselves had titles that originated in
violence. If there ever were humans who acquired the use of land
without forcibly displacing other humans, we have no way of knowing
who they were or who their current descendants might be. There is, in
practice, no way of assigning land to the legitimate successors of
the persons who first claimed land. And to assign titles based on any
fraction of history is to reward the last land seizures that are not
rectified.
The second fundamental problem
with the position of the
homesteading libertarians is that, even if there were previously
unsettled land to be allocated, say a new continent emerging from the
ocean, first grabbing would make no sense as a criterion for
allocating land.
It would be inefficient, for one
thing, as people stampeded to do
whatever was necessary to establish their claims. But that is not
decisive because, if we are concerned with justice, it might be
necessary for us to tolerate inefficiency. But the homesteading
libertarian view makes no sense in terms of justice. "I get it all
because I got here first," isn't justice.
Justice -- the balancing of the
scales -- is the geoist position,
"I
get exclusive access to this natural opportunity because I have left
natural opportunities of equal value for you." (How one compares, in
practice, the value of different natural opportunities is a bit
complex. If you really want to know, you can invite me back for
another lecture.)
Justice is thus a regime in which
persons have the greatest
possible individual liberty, and all acknowledge an obligation to
share equally the value of natural opportunities. Justice is economic
reform--the abolition of all taxes on labor and capital, the
acceptance of individual responsibility, the creation of institutions
that will provide equal sharing the value of natural
opportunities. ... Read the
entire article
Nic Tideman: Applications of
Land Value Taxation to Problems of Environmental Protection, Congestion,
Efficient Resource Use, Population, and Economic Growth
The idea that natural opportunities are everyone's common heritage is often
defended with religious language. John Locke said:
Whether we consider natural reason, which tells us that men, being
once born, have a right to their preservation, and consequently to meat and
drink, and such other things as nature affords for their sustenance, or revelation,
which gives us an account of those grants God made of the world to Adam, and
to Noah, and his sons, 'tis very clear that God, as King David says, Psal.
CXV. xvi. has given the Earth to the children of men, given it to mankind in
common.2
John Locke did not advocate land value taxation. Writing in about 1690, he
said that there was so much unclaimed land in America that no one could properly
complain about the private appropriation of land in Europe.3 Writing
nearly 200 year later, when it was becoming impossible for people to appropriate
good unclaimed land in America, Henry George said:
If we are all here by the equal permission of the creator, we are
all here with an equal title to the enjoyment of his bounty -- with an equal
right to the use of all that nature so impartially offers. This is a right
which is natural and inalienable; it is a right which vests in every human
being as he enters the world, and which during his continuance in the world
can be limited only by the equal rights of others. There is in nature no such
thing as a fee simple in land. There is on earth no power which can rightfully
make a grant of exclusive ownership in land. If all existing men were to unite
to grant away their equal rights, they could not grant away the right of those
who follow them.4
George preceded this argument with a psychological and linguistic one. He
said that our conception of property, of a right of exclusive possession, is
based on the idea that each person has a right to his or her productive powers,
and therefore to what he or she produces. Since no one produced land, no one
can properly claim to own it. 5 ... read
the whole article
Three hundred years ago virtually no one questioned the propriety of
slavery. Even John Locke, that most articulate advocate of human freedom,
invested
in slaves. But over the course of the eighteenth and nineteenth centuries,
amid extreme controversy in some times and places, slavery was nearly
eliminated from the world. With a bit of a lag, a consensus gradually
evolved among
humanity that slavery was wrong, indeed that no distinctions in civil
rights based on race
could be justified.
Two hundred years ago almost no one thought that women should be allowed
to vote. Amid extreme controversy in some times and places, they were granted
voting rights. Now virtually no one argues that women should be denied
any rights that men have. We have not yet arrived at a consensus about
what equality of the sexes means, but we are near a consensus that we should
strive for it. ...
The
Complementary Right of Equal Access to Natural Opportunities
One of the factors that makes the case for secession difficult is the
problem of regional inequality in natural resources. When the people who
called themselves Biafrans sought to secede from Nigeria in the 1960s,
the morality of their claim was undermined by the fact that, if they had
succeeded, they would have taken disproportionate oil resources from the
rest of Nigerians. The limited support for the efforts of the Chechins
to separate from Russia is explained in part by the understanding that,
even though the Chechins have been abused by Russians for centuries and
have never fully acceded to their incorporation into Russia, if Chechniya
were allowed to separate from Russia, that would create a precedent that
would make it difficult to oppose an effort by the people of the sparsely
populated Yakutsia region of Eastern Siberia, rich in oil and diamonds,
to insist that they too have a right to be a separate nation.
Perhaps, a general recognition of a right of secession will need to wait
for another component of moral evolution: a recognition that all persons
have equal claims on the value of natural opportunities. If this were recognized,
then any nation or region with disproportionately great natural resources
would be seen to have an obligation to share the value from using those
resources with those parts of the world that have less than average resources
per capita. This would eliminate the desire to appropriate natural resources
as a reason for secession and as a reason for opposing secession. Signs
of a recognition of the equal claims of all persons on the use of natural
opportunities are slim. One can point to John Locke:
Whether we consider natural Reason, which tells us, the Men,
being once born, have a right to their Preservation, and consequently
to Meat and Drink, and such other things, as Nature affords for their
Subsistence: Or Revelation, which gives us an account of those Grants
God made of the World to Adam, and to Noah, and his Sons, 'tis very clear,
that God, as King David says, Psal. CXV. xvi. has given the Earth to
the Children of Men, given it to Mankind in common.2
Locke goes on to say that every person
has a right to himself, and therefore to the things of value that
are created by combining his efforts with natural
opportunities, "at least where there is as much and as good left in common
for others." He then argues that with so much unclaimed land in America,
no one can justly complain if all of Europe is privately appropriated.
Locke does not address the question of how rights to land should
be handled if there is no unclaimed land. ... read the whole article
John Locke, the natural-law philosopher
whose thought is reflected in the Declaration of Independence and
Bill of Rights, wrote, “the
things of nature are given in common”11 and “no man
could ever have a just power over the life of another by right
of property
in land ...”12 Locke recognized the benefits of private ownership
of land and the right of individuals to possess land — a
right he contended came about when an individual mixed his labor
with the land.
But Locke, in his famous “proviso,” stipulated that
such private ownership would be held on the condition “where
there is enough and as good left in common for others.”13
Though Locke did not explicitly state how that condition could
be met, the payment
to
a community of the rent, which measures the extra productivity
of superior relative to inferior land, would seem to satisfy the
condition,
since
this would keep in common the benefits of holding the better lands.
...
Natural-law philosophers such as John Locke have reasoned that all
human beings have a natural ownership right to their labor and the
products of that labor. The fundamental equality of humanity means
it is fundamentally wrong for some to take away the labor done by
others.31 That notion is almost universally recognized today with
respect to slavery, and some folks are beginning to recognize that
the current tax system—which taxes our earnings and taxes how
we invest or spend those earnings—also violates man’s
natural right to the fruits of his labor. ... read the whole document
Peter Barnes: Capitalism
3.0 — Chapter 2: A Short History of Capitalism (pages 15-32)
In the seventeenth century, John Locke sought to balance the commons
and private property. Like others of his era, he saw that private
property doesn’t exist in a vacuum; it exists in relationship
to a commons, vis-à-vis which there are takings and leavings.
The rationale for private property is that it boosts economic production,
but the commons has a rationale, too: it provides sustenance for
all. Both sides must be respected.
Locke believed that God gave the earth to “mankind in common,” but
that private property is justified because it spurs humans to work.
Whenever a person mixes his labor with nature, he “joins
to it something that is his own, and thereby makes it his property.” But
here Locke added an important proviso: “For this labor being
the unquestionable property of the laborer,” he wrote, “no
man but he can have a right to what that is once joined to, at
least where there is enough, and as good, left in common for others.” In
other words, a person can acquire property, but there’s a
limit to how much he or she can rightfully appropriate. That limit
is set by two considerations: first, it should be no more than
he can join his labor to, and second, it has to leave “enough
and as good” in common for others. This was consistent with
English common law at the time, which held, for example, that a
riparian landowner could withdraw water for his own use, but couldn’t
diminish the supply available to others.
Despite Locke’s quest for balance, the English commons didn’t
last. In the eighteenth and nineteenth centuries, the movement
to enclose and privatize it accelerated greatly. According to historian
Karl Polanyi, this enclosure was the great transformation that
launched the modern era. Local gentry, backed by Parliament, fenced
off village lands and converted them to private holdings. Impoverished
peasants then drifted to cities and became industrial workers.
Landlords invested their agricultural profits in manufacturing,
and modern times, economically speaking, began. ... read
the whole chapter
Peter Barnes: Capitalism
3.0 — Chapter 5: Reinventing the Commons (pages 65-78)
Organizing Principles of the Commons Sector
Property rights, especially the common kind, require competent
institutions to manage them. What we need today, then, along with
more common property, is a set of institutions, distinct from corporations
and government, whose unique and explicit mission is to manage
common property.
I say set of institutions because there will and should be variety.
The commons sector should not be a monoculture like the corporate
sector. Each institution should be appropriate to its particular
asset and locale.
Some of the variety will depend on whether the underlying asset
is limited or inexhaustible. Typically, gifts of nature have limited
capacities; the air can safely absorb only so much carbon dioxide,
the oceans only so many drift nets. Institutions that manage natural
assets must therefore be capable of limiting use. By contrast,
ideas and cultural creations have endless potential for elaboration
and reuse. In these commons, managing institutions should maximize
public access and minimize private tollbooths.
Despite their variations, commons sector institutions would share
a set of organizing principles. Here are the main ones.
LEAVE ENOUGH AND AS GOOD IN COMMON
As Locke argued, it’s okay to privatize parts of the commons
as long as “enough and as good” is left for everyone
forever. Enough in the case of an ecosystem means enough to keep
it alive and healthy. That much, or more, should be part of the
commons, even if parts of the ecosystem are private. In the case
of culture and science, enough means enough to assure a vibrant
public domain. Exclusive licenses, such as patents and copyrights,
should be kept to a minimum.
PUT FUTURE GENERATIONS FIRST
Corporations put the interests of stockholders first, while government
puts the interests of campaign donors and living voters first.
No one at the moment puts future generations first. That’s
Job Number One for the commons sector.
In practice, this means trustees of common property should be
legally accountable to future generations. (We’ll see how
this might work in chapter 6.) They should also be bound by the
precautionary principle: when in doubt, err on the side of safety.
And when faced with a conflict between short-term gain and long-term
preservation, they should be required to choose the latter.
THE MORE THE MERRIER
Whereas private property is inherently exclusive, common property
strives to be inclusive. It always wants more co-owners or participants,
consistent with preservation of the asset.
This organizing principle applies most clearly to commons like
culture and the Internet, where physical limits are absent and
increasing use unleashes synergies galore. It also applies to social
compacts like Social Security and Medicare, which require universal
participation. In these compacts, financial mechanisms express
our solidarity with other members of our national community. They’re
efficient and fair because they include everybody. Were they to
operate under profit-maximizing principles, they’d inevitably
exclude the poor (who couldn’t afford to participate) and
anyone deemed by private insurers to be too risky.
ONE PERSON, ONE SHARE
Modern democratic government is grounded on the principle of one
person, one vote. In the same way, the modern commons sector would
be grounded on the principle of one person, one share. In the case
of scarce natural assets, it will be necessary to distinguish between
usage rights and income rights. It’s impossible for everyone
to use a limited commons equally, but everyone should receive equal
shares of the income derived from selling limited usage rights.
INCLUDE SOME LIQUIDITY
Currently, private property owners enjoy a near-monopoly on the
privilege of receiving property income. But as the Alaska Permanent
Fund shows, it’s possible for common property co-owners
to receive income too.
Income sharing would end private property’s monopoly not
only on liquidity, but also on attention. People would notice common
property if they got income from it. They’d care about it,
think about it, and talk about it. Concern for invisible commons
would soar.
Common property liquidity has to be designed carefully, though.
Since common property rights are birthrights, they shouldn’t
be tradeable the way corporate shares are. This means commons owners
wouldn’t reap capital gains. Instead, they’d retain
their shared income stakes throughout their lives, and through
such stakes, share in rent, royalties, interest, and dividends.
... read
the whole chapter
Peter Barnes: Capitalism
3.0 — Chapter 7: Universal Birthrights (pages 101-116)
The Idea of Birthrights
John Locke’s response to royalty’s claim of divine
right was the idea of everyone’s inherent right to life,
liberty, and property. Thomas Jefferson, in drafting America’s
Declaration of Independence, changed Locke’s trinity to life,
liberty, and the pursuit of happiness. These, Jefferson and his
collaborators agreed, are gifts from the creator that can’t
be taken away. Put slightly differently, they’re universal
birthrights.
The Constitution and its amendments added meat to these elegant
bones. They guaranteed such birthrights as free speech, due process,
habeas corpus, speedy public trials, and secure homes and property.
Wisely, the Ninth Amendment affirmed that “the enumeration
in the Constitution, of certain rights, shall not be construed
to deny or disparage others retained by the people.” In that
spirit, others have since been added.
If we were to analyze the expansion of American birthrights, we’d
see a series of waves. The first wave consisted of rights against
the state. The second included rights against unequal treatment
based on race, nationality, gender, or sexual orientation. The
third wave — which, historically speaking, is just beginning — consists
of rights not against things, but for things — free public
education, collective bargaining for wages, security in old age.
They can be thought of as rights necessary for the pursuit of happiness.
What makes this latest wave of birthrights strengthen community
is their universality. If some Americans could enjoy free public
education while others couldn’t, the resulting inequities
would divide rather than unite us as a nation. The universality
of these rights puts everyone in the same boat. It spreads risk,
responsibility, opportunity, and reward across race, gender, economic
classes, and generations. It makes us a nation rather than a collection
of isolated individuals.
Universality is also what distinguishes the commons sector from
the corporate sector. The starting condition for the corporate
sector, as we’ve seen, is that the top 5 percent owns more
shares than everyone else. The starting condition for the commons
sector, by contrast, is one person, one share.
The standard argument against third wave universal birthrights
is that, while they might be nice in theory, in practice they are
too expensive. They impose an unbearable burden on “the economy” — that
is, on the winners in unfettered markets. Much better, therefore,
to let everyone — including poor children and the sick — fend
for themselves. In fact, the opposite is often true: universal
birthrights, as we’ll see, can be cheaper and more efficient
than individual acquisition. Moreover, they are always fairer.
How far we might go down the path of extending universal birthrights
is anyone’s guess, but we’re now at the point where,
economically speaking, we can afford to go farther. Without great
difficulty, we could add three birthrights to our economic operating
system: one would pay everyone a regular dividend, the second would
give every child a start-up stake, and the third would reduce and
share medical costs. Whether we add these birthrights or not isn’t
a matter of economic ability, but of attitude and politics.
Why attitude? Americans suffer from a number of confusions. We
think it’s “wrong” to give people “something
for nothing,” despite the fact that corporations take common
wealth for nothing all the time. We believe the poor are poor and
the rich are rich because they deserve to be, but don’t consider
that millions of Americans work two or three jobs and still can’t
make ends meet. Plus, we think tinkering with the “natural” distribution
of income is “socialism,” or “big government,” or
some other manifestation of evil, despite the fact that our current
distribution of income isn’t “natural” at all,
but rigged from the get-go by maldistributed property.
The late John Rawls, one of America’s leading philosophers,
distinguished between pre distribution of property and re distribution
of income. Under income re distribution, money is taken from “winners” and
transferred to “losers.” Understandably, this isn’t
popular with winners, who tend to control government and the media.
Under property pre distribution, by contrast, the playing field
is leveled by spreading property ownership before income is generated.
After that, there’s no need for income redistribution; property
itself distributes income to all. According to Rawls, while income
re distribution creates dependency, property predistribution empowers.
But how can we spread property ownership without taking property
from some and giving it to others? The answer lies in the commons — wealth
that already belongs to everyone. By propertizing (without privatizing)
some of that wealth, we can make everyone a property owner.
What’s interesting is that, for purely ecological reasons,
we need to propertize (without privatizing) some natural wealth
now. This twenty-first century necessity means we have a chance
to save the planet, and as a bonus, add a universal birthright.
... read
the whole chapter
Peter Barnes: Capitalism
3.0 — Chapter 8: Sharing Culture (pages 117-134)
The Statute of Queen Anne, passed by the English Parliament in
1710, gave authors, not printers, title to their works. Such
title was in the form of an exclusive right for fourteen years,
with an option to renew for the same period. Thereafter, works
would enter what we now call the public domain, and anyone could
reprint them without further compensating the author. The idea
was to reward authors sufficiently to induce them to write, but
once they’d been fairly paid, to have literature circulate
as widely and as cheaply as possible.
A leading advocate of this new arrangement was John Locke. As
with landed property, Locke sought to balance the interest of the
laborer who adds value with that of the commons that stores and
shares value. In a memorandum to Parliament, he argued that it
was “unreasonable and injurious to learning” to grant
exclusive rights to print classic texts; the “liberty, to
any one, of printing them, is certainly the way to have them the
cheaper and the better.” As for “authors that now live
and write,” he proposed “to limit their property to
a certain number of years after . . . the first printing of the
book.”
In this spirit, the U.S. Constitution gave Congress authority “to
promote the Progress of Science and useful Arts, by securing for
limited Times to Authors and Inventors the exclusive Right to their
respective Writings and Discoveries.” Shortly thereafter,
in 1790, the first American copyright law gave authors the same
deal as in Britain: exclusive rights for fourteen years, with an
option to renew for another fourteen. After that, their work entered
the public domain. The idea wasn’t so much to expand intellectual
property rights as to set boundaries on them. Indeed, what we call
intellectual property today was then considered a monopoly privilege
granted by the state, not a right belonging to a creator.
For nearly two centuries, this arrangement worked brilliantly.
There was no lack of creativity on either side of the Atlantic.
But starting about thirty years ago, large entertainment companies
began tipping the balance from the public domain to the private.
Led by the Walt Disney Company, the corporations pushed Congress
to extend copyright terms, first to seventy-five years and then
to ninety-five. (The extensions occurred whenever Mickey Mouse
was about to enter the public domain.) One consequence is that
the public domain has been marginalized; corporations now take
from the commons and give nothing back. Another is that the experience
of culture has been altered; we’re now consumers of culture
rather than participants. ... read
the whole chapter
|
To
share this page with a friend: right click, choose "send," and
add your comments.
|
|
Red
links have not been visited; .
Green
links are pages you've seen |
Essential Documents
pertinent to this theme:
|
|