Equity
in Taxation
Henry George: The Common Sense of Taxation (1881
article)
Evidently this regard for the general good is the true principle of taxation.
The more it is examined the more clearly it will be seen that there is no
valid reason why we should, in any case, attempt to tax all property. That
equality should be the rule and aim of taxation is true, and this for the
reason given in the Declaration of Independence, that all men are created
equal. But equality does not require that all men should be taxed alike,
or that all things should be taxed alike. It merely requires that whatever
taxes are imposed shall be equally imposed upon the persons or things in
like conditions or situations; it merely requires that no citizen shall be
given an advantage, or put at a disadvantage, as compared with other citizens.
The true purposes of government are well stated in the preamble to the
Constitution of the United States, as they are in the Declaration of Independence.
To insure the general peace, to promote the general welfare, to secure to
each individual the inalienable rights to life, liberty, and the pursuit
of happiness — these are the proper ends of government, and are therefore
the ends which in every scheme of taxation should be kept in mind. ...
To consider the nature of property of this kind is again to see a clear
distinction. That distinction is not, as the lawyers have it, between movables
and immovables, between personal property and real estate. The true distinction
is between property which is, and property which is not, the result of human
labor; or, to use the terms of political economy, between land and wealth.
For, in any precise use of the term, land is not wealth, any more than labor
is wealth. Land and labor are the factors of production. Wealth is such result
of their union as retains the capacity of ministering to human desire. A
lot and the house which stands upon it are alike property, alike have a tangible
value, and are alike classed as real estate. But there are between them the
most essential differences. The one is the free gift of Nature, the other
the result of human exertion; the one exists from generation to generation,
while men come and go; the other is constantly tending to decay, and can
only be preserved by continual exertion. To the one, the right of exclusive
possession, which makes it individual property, can, like the right of property
in slaves, be traced to nothing but municipal law; to the other, the right
of exclusive property springs clearly from those natural relations which
are among the primary perceptions of the human mind. Nor are these mere abstract
distinctions. They are distinctions of the first importance in determining
what should and what should not be taxed.
For, keeping in mind the fact that all wealth is the result of human exertion,
it is clearly seen that, having in view the promotion of the general prosperity,
it is the height of absurdity to tax wealth for purposes of revenue while
there remains, unexhausted by taxation, any value attaching to land. We may
tax land values as much as we please, without in the slightest degree lessening
the amount of land, or the capabilities of land, or the inducement to use
land. But we cannot tax wealth without lessening the inducement to the production
of wealth, and decreasing the amount of wealth. We might take the whole value
of land in taxation, so as to make the ownership of land worth nothing, and
the land would still remain, and be as useful as before. The effect would
be to throw land open to users free of price, and thus to increase its capabilities,
which are brought out by increased population. But impose anything like such
taxation upon wealth, and the inducement to the production of wealth would
be gone. Movable wealth would be hidden or carried off, immovable wealth
would be suffered to go to decay, and where was prosperity would soon be
the silence of desolation.
And the reason of this difference is clear. The possession of wealth is
the inducement to the exertion necessary to the production and maintenance
of wealth. Men do not work for the pleasure of working, but to get the things
their work will give them. And to tax the things that are produced by exertion
is to lessen the inducement to exertion. But over and above the benefit to
the possessor, which is the stimulating motive to the production of wealth,
there is a benefit to the community, for no matter how selfish he may be,
it is utterly impossible for any one to entirely keep to himself the benefit
of any desirable thing he may possess. These diffused benefits when localized
give value to land, and this may be taxed without in any wise diminishing
the incentive to production.
To illustrate: A man builds a fine house or large factory in a poorly improved
neighborhood. To tax this building and its adjuncts is to make him pay for
his enterprise and expenditure — to take from him part of his natural
reward. But the improvement thus made has given new beauty or life to the
neighborhood, making it a more desirable place than before for the erection
of other houses or factories, and additional value is given to land all about.
Now to tax improvements is not only to deprive of his proper reward the man
who has made the improvement, but it is to deter others from making similar
improvements. But, instead of taxing improvements, to tax these land values
is to leave the natural inducement to further improvement in full force,
and at the same time to keep down an obstacle to further improvement, which,
under the present system, improvement itself tends to raise. For the advance
of land values which follows improvement, and even the expectation of improvement,
makes further improvement more costly.
See how unjust and short-sighted is this system. Here is a man who, gathering
what little capital he can, and taking his family, starts West to find a
place where he can make himself a home. He must travel long distances; for,
though he will pass plenty of land nobody is using, it is held at prices
too high for him. Finally he will go no further, and selects a place where,
since the creation of the world, the soil, so far as we know, has never felt
a plowshare. But here, too, in nine cases out of ten, he will find the speculator
has been ahead of him, for the speculator moves quicker, and has superior
means of information to the emigrant. Before he can put this land to the
use for which nature intended it, and to which it is for the general good
that it should be put, he must make terms with some man who in all probability
never saw the land, and never dreamed of using it, and who, it may be, resides
in some city, thousands of miles away. In order to get permission to use
this land, he must give up a large part of the little capital which is seed-wheat
to him, and perhaps in addition mortgage his future labor for years. Still
he goes to work: he works himself, and his wife works, and his children work — work
like horses, and live in the hardest and dreariest manner. Such a man deserves
encouragement, not discouragement; but on him taxation falls with peculiar
severity. Almost everything that he has to buy — groceries, clothing,
tools — is largely raised in price by a system of tariff taxation which
cannot add to the price of the grain or hogs or cattle that he has to sell.
And when the assessor comes around he is taxed on the improvements he has
made, although these improvements have added not only to the value of surrounding
land, but even to the value of land in distant commercial centers. Not merely
this, but, as a general rule, his land, irrespective of the improvements,
will be assessed at a higher rate than unimproved land around it, on the
ground that "productive property" ought to pay more than "unproductive
property" — a principle just the reverse of the correct one, for
the man who makes land productive adds to the general prosperity, while the
man who keeps land unproductive stands in the way of the general prosperity,
is but a dog-in-the-manger, who prevents others from using what he will not
use himself.
Or, take the case of the railroads. That railroads are a public benefit
no one will dispute. We want more railroads, and want them to reduce their
fares and freight. Why then should we tax them? for taxes upon railroads
deter from railroad building, and compel higher charges. Instead of taxing
the railroads, is it not clear that we should rather tax the increased value
which they give to land? To tax railroads is to check railroad building,
to reduce profits, and compel higher rates; to tax the value they give to
land is to increase railroad business and permit lower rates. The elevated
railroads, for instance, have opened to the overcrowded population of New
York the wide, vacant spaces of the upper part of the island. But this great
public benefit is neutralized by the rise in land values. Because these vacant
lots can be reached more cheaply and quickly, their owners demand more for
them, and so the public gain in one way is offset in another, while the roads
lose the business they would get were not building checked by the high prices
demanded for lots. The increase of land values, which the elevated roads
have caused, is not merely no advantage to them — it is an injury;
and it is clearly a public injury. The elevated railroads ought not to be
taxed. The more profit they make, with the better conscience can they be
asked to still further reduce fares. It is the increased land values which
they have created that ought to be taxed, for taxing them will give the public
the full benefit of cheap fares.
So with railroads everywhere. And so not alone with railroads, but with
all industrial enterprises. So long as we consider that community most prosperous
which increases most rapidly in wealth, so long is it the height of absurdity
for us to tax wealth in any of its beneficial forms. We should tax what we
want to repress, not what we want to encourage. We should tax that which
results from the general prosperity, not that which conduces to it. It is
the increase of population, the extension of cultivation, the manufacture
of goods, the building of houses and ships and railroads, the accumulation
of capital, and the growth of commerce that add to the value of land — not
the increase in the value of land that induces the increase of population
and increase of wealth. It is not that the land of Manhattan Island is now
worth hundreds of millions where, in the time of the early Dutch settlers,
it was only worth dollars, that there are on it now so many more people,
and so much more wealth. It is because of the increase of population and
the increase of wealth that the value of the land has so much increased.
Increase of land values tends of itself to repel population and prevent improvement.
And thus the taxation of land values, unlike taxation of other property,
does not tend to prevent the increase of wealth, but rather to stimulate
it. It is the taking of the golden egg, not the choking of the goose that
lays it.
Every consideration of policy and ethics squares with this conclusion.
The tax upon land values is the most economically perfect of all taxes. It
does not raise prices; it maybe collected at least cost, and with the utmost
ease and certainty; it leaves in full strength all the springs of production;
and, above all, it consorts with the truest equality and the highest justice.
For, to take for the common purposes of the community that value which results
from the growth of the community, and to free industry and enterprise and
thrift from burden and restraint, is to leave to each that which he fairly
earns, and to assert the first and most comprehensive of equal rights — the
equal right of all to the land on which, and from which, all must live.
Thus it is that the scheme of taxation which conduces to the greatest production
is also that which conduces to the fairest distribution, and that in the
proper adjustment of taxation lies not merely the possibility of enormously
increasing the general wealth, but the solution of these pressing social
and political problems which spring from unnatural inequality in the distribution
of wealth.
"There is," says M. de Laveleye, in concluding that work in which
he shows that the first perceptions of mankind have everywhere recognized
a most vital distinction between property in land and property which results
from labor, — "there is in human affairs one system which is the
best; it is not that system which always exists, otherwise why should we
desire to change it; but it is that system which should exist for the greatest
good of humanity. God knows it, and wills it; man's duty it is to discover
and establish it." ... read the whole article
Louis Post: Outlines of Louis F. Post's
Lectures, with Illustrative Notes and Charts (1894)
4. CONFORMITY TO GENERAL PRINCIPLES OF TAXATION
The single tax conforms most closely to the essential principles of Adam
Smith's four classical maxims, which are stated best by Henry George 19 as
follows:
The best tax by which public revenues can be raised is evidently that which
will closest conform to the following conditions:
- That it bear as lightly as possible upon production — so as least
to check the increase of the general fund from which taxes must be paid
and the community maintained. 20
- That it be easily and cheaply collected, and fall as directly as may
be upon the ultimate payers — so as to take from the people as little
as possible in addition to what it yields the government. 21
- That it be certain — so as to give the least opportunity for tyranny
or corruption on the part of officials, and the least temptation to law-breaking
and evasion on the part of the tax-payers. 22
- That it bear equally — so as to give no citizen an advantage or
put any at a disadvantage, as compared with others. 23
19. "Progress and Poverty," book viii. ch.iii.
20. This is the second part of Adam Smith's fourth maxim.
He states it as follows: "Every tax ought to be so contrived as
both to take out and to keep out of the pockets of the people as little
as possible over and above what it brings into the public treasury of
the state. A tax may either take out or keep out of the pockets of the
people a great deal more than it brings into the public treasury in the
four following ways: . . . Secondly, it may obstruct the industry of
the people, and discourage them from applying to certain branches of
business which might give maintenance and employment to great multitudes.
While it obliges the people to pay, it may thus diminish or perhaps destroy
some of the funds which might enable them more easily to do so."
21. This is the first part of Adam Smith's fourth maxim,
in which he condemns a tax that takes out of the pockets of the people
more than it brings into the public treasury.
22. This is Adam Smith's second maxim. He states it as
follows: "The tax which each individual is bound to pay ought to
be certain and not arbitrary. The time of payment, the manner of payment,
the quantity to be paid, ought all to be clear and plain to the contributor
and to every other person. Where it is otherwise, every person subject
to the tax is put more or less in the power of the tax gatherer."
23. This is Adam Smith's first maxim. He states it as
follows: "The subjects of every state ought to contribute towards
the support of the government as nearly as possible in proportion to
their respective abilities, that is to say, in proportion to the revenue
which they respectively enjoy under the protection of the state. The
expense of government to the individuals of a great nation is like the
expense of management to the joint tenants of a great estate, who are
all obliged to contribute in proportion to their respective interests
in the estate. In the observation or neglect of this maxim consists what
is called the equality or inequality of taxation."
In changing this Mr. George says ("Progress
and Poverty," book viii, ch. iii, subd. 4): "Adam Smith
speaks of incomes as enjoyed 'under the protection of the state'; and
this is the ground upon which the equal taxation of all species of
property is commonly insisted upon — that it is equally protected
by the state. The basis of this idea is evidently that the enjoyment
of property is made possible by the state — that there is a value
created and maintained by the community; which is justly called upon
to meet community expenses. Now, of what values is this true? Only
of the value of land. This is a value that does not arise until a community
is formed, and that, unlike other values, grows with the growth of
the community. It only exists as the community exists. Scatter again
the largest community, and land, now so valuable, would have no value
at all. With every increase of population the value of land rises;
with every decrease it falls. This is true of nothing else save of
things which, like the ownership of land, are in their nature monopolies."
Adam Smith's third maxim refers only to conveniency of
payment, and gives countenance to indirect taxation, which is in conflict
with the principle of his fourth maxim. Mr. George properly excludes
it. ...
c. Certainty
No other tax, direct or indirect, conforms so closely to the third maxim. "Land
lies out of doors." It cannot be hidden; it cannot be "accidentally" overlooked.
Nor can its value be seriously misstated. Neither under-appraisement nor
over-appraisement to any important degree is possible without the connivance
of the whole community. 27 The land values of a neighborhood are matters
of common knowledge. Any intelligent resident can justly appraise them, and
every other intelligent resident can fairly test the appraisement. Therefore,
the tyranny, corruption, fraud, favoritism, and evasions that are so common
in connection with the taxation of imports, manufactures, incomes, personal
property, and buildings — the values of which, even when the object
itself cannot be hidden, are so distinctly matters of minute special knowledge
that only experts can fairly appraise them — would be out of the question
if the single tax were substituted for existing fiscal methods. 28 ...
d. Equality
In respect of the fourth maxim the single tax bears more equally— that
is to say, more justly — than any other tax. It is the only tax that
falls upon the taxpayer in proportion to the pecuniary benefits he receives
from the public; 29 and its tendency, accelerating with the increase of the
tax, is to leave every one the full fruit of his own productive enterprise
and effort. 30
29 The benefits of government are not the only public
benefits whose value attaches exclusively to land. Communal development
from whatever cause produces the same effect. But as it is under the
protection of government that land-owners are able to maintain ownership
of land and through that to enjoy the pecuniary benefits of advancing
social conditions, government confers upon them as a class not only the
pecuniary benefits of good government but also the pecuniary benefits
of progress in general.
30. "Here are two men of equal incomes — that
of the one derived from the exertion of his labor, that of the other
from the rent of land. Is it just that they should equally contribute
to the expenses of the state? Evidently not. The income of the one represents
wealth he creates and adds to the general wealth of the state; the income
of the other represents merely wealth that he takes from the general
stock, returning nothing." — Progress and Poverty, book
viii, ch. iii, subd. 4.
... read the book
Bill Batt: Painless Taxation
Abstract
Real tax reform could do away with those taxes that are resented
by the large proportion of our population. We could replace all taxes on
wages and on interest by instead taxing economic rent. Rent is windfall income;
it is income that arises not from the efforts of any person or corporation;
it comes about as a surplus gain from common social enterprise. There is
ample moral warrant for society to lay claim to that which it has created,
as well as to that which no individual or party has earned. Analysis increasingly
makes clear that economic rent in all its forms is far larger than official
government figures indicate; in fact it is likely sufficient to supplant
all current taxes on labor and capital (wages and interest) which are acknowledged
to have so many negative effects. Recovering economic rent in all its manifestations
by taxing its various bases actually can foster economic performance and
yield other benefits that make it the natural source of revenue for governments.
Such a tax is essentially painless. ...
Tax Principles
The starting points should be the lessons that have been learned over the
course of the past three hundred and more years about what is a good tax.
Most basic textbooks in public finance enumerate them in very clear form,
and they constitute benchmarks against which to measure the soundness of
any particular tax. They are listed as few as three or as many as eight such
principles but little disagreement exists as to their substance, regardless
of ideology or government. Most commonly enumerated are neutrality, efficiency,
equity, administrability, simplicity, stability, sufficiency.[3] Tax
theorists typically measure revenue structures according to any or all of
these criteria: ...
The principle of equity is central to any discussion of
tax design. Tax design requires concern with both what is fair and the extent
to which it must sometimes be compromised to satisfy the other principal
criteria. Fairness can be evaluated according to what is termed "horizontal
equity" -- the extent to which those in similar circumstances will pay
similar tax burdens, and "vertical equity" -- how well those in
different classes bear different burdens in the tax structure. It is this
latter perspective that leads to the use of terms like "proportional," "progressive," and "regressive" in
referring to tax structures. A tax is progressive with respect to income
if the ratio of tax revenue to income rises when moving up the income scale,
proportional if the ratio is constant, and regressive if the ratio declines.
There is an ancillary question of whether taxing to reach greater equity
should employ measures of income or of wealth, difficult as this is to measure.
Such questions of equity are a matter particularly central when discussing
the property tax. ... read the whole article
Bill Batt: Comment on Parts of
the NYS Legislative Tax Study Commission's 1985 study “Who Pays New
York Taxes?”
... This last caveat suggests what is likely the most critical failing of
the Report. The use of an income snapshot as the basis for measuring the
effective
tax burden on owners of real property reflects a misunderstanding of how
tax equity should be construed. The value of property titles is a measure
of wealth, and is likely to have little if any bearing on any momentary snapshot
of income in a household. This confusion lies at the very core of difficulties
in assessing the fairness of the property tax. Several studies of tax equity
involving the real property tax fail to recognize that they are using income
as a benchmark for analysis, even while the tax is upon wealth. ... read
the whole commentary
Bill Batt: How Our Towns Got That
Way (1996 speech)
There were many arguments to be
made for the classical tradition,
the result of which would be to rely upon payment of rent of land
according to its value to society. George recognized that land value
is largely a function of how society has elected to invest in any
general neighborhood; there is no argument for any one titleholder to
reap the reward of what others have invested. Gaffney points out
that, from the standpoint of economic theory, the framework had the
following virtues:
- It reconciled common land rights with private tenure, free
markets and modern capitalism, a growing and persistent problem as the
industrial society took hold.
- It enabled the lowering of taxes on labor without raising
taxes
on capital.
- It reconciled equity and
efficiency. It constituted a progressive
tax because land is concentrated so much among the wealthy and because
the tax cannot be shifted. It was efficient because it is
neutral among
different land-use options.
- It constituted no disincentive to business location or
population
settlement. In this way it encouraged the most efficient land use and
discouraged sprawl.
- It created jobs without inflation, and raised government
revenue
without any penalty upon its base.
- It strengthened public revenues and at the same time
promotes
economy in government.
Those economists who today still
persistently hold to the view
that there is something special about land that make it unwise to
treat as a form of capital are known as Georgists. They represent a
small minority of the economics profession, but, little known as they
are, they are among its most esteemed members. ...
The principle of equity is
central to any discussion of tax
design. Tax design requires concern with both what is fair and the
extent to which it must sometimes be compromised to satisfy the other
principal criteria. Fairness can be evaluated according to what is
termed "horizontal equity" the extent to which those in similar
circumstances will pay similar tax burdens, and "vertical equity" how
well those in different classes bear different burdens in the tax
structure. It is this latter perspective that leads to the use of
terms like "proportional," "progressive," and "regressive" in
referring to tax structures. A tax is progressive with respect to
income if the ratio of tax revenue to income rises when moving up the
income scale, proportional if the ratio is constant, and regressive
if the ratio declines. There is an ancillary question of whether
taxing to reach greater equity should employ measures of income or of
wealth, difficult as this is to measure. Such questions of equity are
a matter particularly central when discussing the property tax. This
is because people capitalize their income in the course of a lifetime
frequently in property. Although claims are often made to the
contrary and really comprehensive studies have yet to be done,
available studies suggest that the property tax is really highly
progressive, especially for the land component.... read
the whole article
Bill Batt: Who Says Cities are Poor? They Just
Don't Know How to Tax Their Wealth!
The Perfect Tax
In the final analysis, a tax should be evaluated according to the tenets
of sound tax theory that have evolved over the course of recent centuries,
and
much of what has been said above is recaptured by a review of those principles.
These measures of what is a "good" tax or a "bad" tax are
often listed differently in textbooks, but they are largely agreed upon. Failure
to conform to these venerable benchmarks is by itself sufficient cause to explain
an economy's faltering — a particularly noteworthy example today
is the city of Philadelphia which appears to have done everything backward!
It taxes
income, sales, building capital and even business privilege, the result
being that its fisc is destitute.[20] The
principles by which to measure tax design are enumerated here so as to
make quite clear how recapturing economic rent in the form of taxes — in all
the several forms where 'land' can be identified — constitutes the
best method of financing government services and the most advantageous
to cities.[21]
The first measure of a good tax is its neutrality. A neutral tax in no way
alters the behavior of its partners from what would transpire were there
no tax at all. A simple example illustrates the case: today many consumers
will
travel to alternate jurisdictions to avoid paying a sales tax on particular
items, be they food, medication, clothing, or whatever. Taxes fully absorbed
("capitalized") in a market price such as land taxes in no way
distort behavior, the volume of transactions, or gross prices. They are
neutral.
A tax should also be efficient. To be sure, efficiency has many meanings even
in economics. But here, rather than speaking of the administrative efficiency
of its collection as will be addressed below, the measure is whether and how
much it constitutes an excess burden on the economy, thereby slowing down performance
and market vitality. Many taxes, as was mentioned earlier, exert so much drag
on market transactions that they are destructive, however much revenue is brought
to government coffers. Because land has a fixed supply there is no excess burden
at all.
People are frequently most concerned about the fairness of a tax, which
is typically measured according to both horizontal and vertical equity. Horizontal
equity means that those in similar circumstances will bear similar burdens.
Vertical equity prescribes that those with greater resources will pay more.
Although studies have yet to show this, land taxes are likely the most "progressive" of
any levy, as tenants bear no passed-through burden at all.[22] Not
only does no household or office tenant bear any tax burden, locational
sites distant from the urban core, mostly homeowners and farmers, typically
find
their burden reduced. Vacant or underused lots in high value areas pick
up the difference, employing a design that employs an alternate criterion
of equity:
taxing according to use. "Paying for what you take and not for what you
make" encourages efficient consumption of space and resources in an
automatic and non-coercive manner. The one-third of households that own
no land are relieved
of all taxes, and residential and non-residential property owners split
the rest. Farmers, whose land is typically of inconsequential value relative
to
sites in urban areas, are likely to pay little if anything even if they
are not already protected by other save-harmless provisions. By eliminating
taxes
on building improvements they typically enjoy savings just as do other
businesses.
All this makes for a far simpler and more comprehensible system of taxation.
Land taxes are totally transparent, impossible to evade, and therefore
much more administrable. This further engenders the legitimacy of taxation
and of
government itself. What it also does is assure stability to the tax system,
for the reason that land values are not subject to the variations and vacillations
that other tax bases frequently have. Indeed, the removal of economic rent
from locational sites discourages speculative bubbles and the related economic
cycles that are associated with them. This greater stability and reliability
is to the advantage of every sector of the economy — private, public,
and non-profit.
A tax that collects economic rent offers a win-win proposition to every
sector of the community — except to those who speculate in land. But
who wants to favor land speculators? They are not held in high regard anywhere;
their
destructive behavior is the bane of cities, recognized everywhere for what
it is: parasitic and passive. Speculators provide no added value to a community's
well-being, and taxing rent is a foolproof means by which to eliminate
it. Land speculation is highest where the most rent can be privately captured,
but it forces those who choose to develop to look to sub-optimal locations
when the primary locations they hoped for are held off the market for opportunistic
gain. By collecting rent, primary choice locations become available for
use
and to facilitate the development of land use configurations ideal for
the economic health and efficient allocation. Urban ambience is improved,
public
sector service costs are reduced, and sprawl development is stemmed. ... read the whole article
Frank Stilwell and Kirrily Jordan: The
Political Economy of Land: Putting Henry George in His Place
One might expect such arguments to have led to the advocacy of land
nationalisation. But George thought this unnecessary because a tax on land
could be effective
in capturing the economic surplus arising from land ownership. This tax
would generate all the revenue necessary to fund public expenditures. George
thought that such a land tax would permit the removal of other taxes on
labour and capital, which he regarded as inherently inefficient. He argued
that taxes on incomes, sales, and payrolls, for example, acted as disincentives
to production and active endeavour, thereby stifling economic growth and
creating a barrier to full employment. A land tax, by contrast, would be
both economically efficient and more equitable in its distributional effects.
... read the whole article
|
To
share this page with a friend: right click, choose "send," and
add your comments.
|
|
Red
links have not been visited; .
Green
links are pages you've seen |
Essential Documents
pertinent to this theme:
|
|